15

I'm interested in introducing my middle school children to proofs using significant examples (i.e., not just basic geometry proofs in an intro to trig textbook). They have a pre-algebra background (so, polynomials, powers, greatest common factor, etc.). I can think of several proofs off the top of my head:

Proof of the irrationality of $\sqrt{2}$

Cantor's diagonalization proof

Pythagorean's rearrangement proof (and other proofs of the Pythagorean theorem).

What other significant proofs are there that would be explainable to someone with a pre-algebra background?

Parcly Taxel
  • 103,344
Tiberius
  • 167
  • 1
    If you allow things that are like polynomials, you can introduce something like the geometric series or power series in general. If you want to keep it more basic, there are Diophantine equations as well (using modular arithmetic). I would also suggest throwing in some counterexamples to ideas that seem intuitive, if you can find any that are suitable (if intuition suffices, topology has plenty of examples that can be explained using pictures). – Clayton May 29 '21 at 13:37
  • 13
    Prove that there are infinitely many prime numbers. – Peter Szilas May 29 '21 at 13:40
  • 5
    The dissection proof of $a^2-b^2=(a+b)(a-b)$ is one possibility. – kimchi lover May 29 '21 at 13:41
  • 6
    You might get better answers at https://matheducators.stackexchange.com/ – Ethan Bolker May 29 '21 at 13:43
  • 2
    They have a pre-algebra background (so, polynomials, --- Do they have only a pre-algebra background (which would certainly exclude polynomials) or a background in algebra that includes polynomials? To me, prealgebra consists of material one learns just BEFORE algebra, such as numerical percent problems, conversions between units (e.g. how many inches in 3.8 yards), possibly substituting numbers into simple algebraic formulas (but not manipulating formulas), verifying solutions to simple equations by substitution (but not using algebraic methods to find the solutions), etc. – Dave L. Renfro May 29 '21 at 14:00
  • Pre-calculus background or pre-algebra background? – Paul May 29 '21 at 14:15
  • 4
    Apologies, their “pre-algebra” course (Kahn Academy) includes material that might be better described as “algebra lite,” so very basic symbol manipulation, basic factorization, etc. – Tiberius May 29 '21 at 14:17
  • 3
    Some mod arithmetic proofs. A number is divisible by 3 if the sum of its digits is divisible by 3. Same for 9's. Explore a number divisible by 11 when? Another is to count the number of factors of a number given it's prime factorization. – Paul May 29 '21 at 14:19
  • Shouldn’t they already have had geometry by then? Middle school geometry has a lot of proofs. – RBarryYoung May 29 '21 at 22:24
  • That's why I added "not just basic geometry proofs in an intro to trig textbook." Middle school geometry has a lot of proofs, but they're almost commonsensical and aren't terribly insightful. – Tiberius May 29 '21 at 23:13
  • Various topics from Finite Mathematics, by Kemeny, Snell, & Thompson. – DanielWainfleet May 30 '21 at 01:13
  • 1
    A chessboard with the upper left and lower right squares removed cannot be covered by dominoes. – awkward May 30 '21 at 13:16

4 Answers4

9

Here a couple of examples I can think of:


*Actually, at least two digits occur infinitely often. That's because if only $1$ digit appeared infinitely often, then there would be a point in the decimal representation of $\pi$ where the digits would only consist of a single number. This would make $\pi$ rational.

**Don't prove this by contradiction. See here.

Joe
  • 19,636
5

If you mention Cantor's diagonal argument then you should also consider Julius König's proof of the Schröder–Bernstein theorem – the one that makes chains of function applications between two sets to prove a bijection. This is significant because it ultimately allows the notion of cardinality by establishing a bijection to some standard set.

In graph theory there is the Seven Bridges problem and the proof of its lack of solution, which only relies on following a path in and out of a vertex (and also indicates that proofs don't have to show something positively). In number theory there is Euclid's proof of the infinitude of primes, as mentioned in comments.

Combinatorics and its "twin city" of probability are full of simple but profound results too. The Fibonacci numbers appear everywhere – the proof that they enumerate tilings of a $1×n$ rectangle by single squares and dominoes is but one example in the former topic; gambler's ruin and the Monty Hall problem are examples in the latter (these shed a little light on the psychology of betting and why people lose when betting in the long run).


There has never been something called "pre-algebra" or "middle school" in Singapore's educational system, and furthermore I had gifted education (Integrated Programme, NUS High School). Some of the examples above may therefore be too high-level.

Parcly Taxel
  • 103,344
4

Little Fermat? Pick a prime $p$ and a number $n$. Then $n^p-n$ is a multiple of $p$.
If $n$ is a multiple of $p$ we are done. So suppose it isn't.
Multiplying the numbers from $1$ to $p-1$ by $n$, then taking the remainder, shuffles the numbers. (The difference between any two is not a multiple of $p$ so they are all different.) So $1×2×3×...×(p-1)$ and $n×2n×3n×...(p-1)n$ leave the same remainder when you divide by $p$.
So $(n^{p-1}-1)(p-1)!$ is a multiple of $p$. $(p-1)!$ is not, so $n^{p-1}-1$ must be.

Empy2
  • 50,853
  • Another accessible proof of this is to consider necklaces of $p$ beads, with $n$ colors available for each bead. Because $p$ is prime, the only color patterns that are unchanged under some cyclic permutation are the $n$ patterns with all beads the same color. The remaining $n^p-n$ color patterns must therefore come in sets of $p$. – Will Orrick Jun 03 '21 at 03:25
  • Ooh, that's nice. – Empy2 Jun 03 '21 at 04:26
1

In Ontario I have met many high-school graduates who are vague or confused about $\Bbb R,$ especially on the issue of infinitesimals, that is, whether a number can be positive but less than every member of $\Bbb Q+.$ I think this is because they were not taught properly. I'm sure they never heard of a Dedekind cut. I suggest you give an axiomatic def'n of $\Bbb R,$ and show from the def'n that (i) the Archimedean property, (ii) the non-existence of infinitesimals in $\Bbb R$, (iii) the order-density (in $\Bbb R$) of $\Bbb Q$ & of its complement, (iv) every non-empty subset of $\Bbb R$ with an upper (lower) bound has a lub (glb) and from this deduce that $\sqrt 2$ exists in $\Bbb R.$

I think it would be helpful to emphasize that these follow from the def'n of a certain structure ($\Bbb R$) but that we can also define larger structures (e.g. the hyper-reals), so we cannot derive properties of the "real" numbers without a definition. Without a def'n it's like trying to prove that widgets are green.