3

Given $C \subseteq \mathbb{R}$ closed, find a sequence such for every point in $C$ there is a subsequence of your sequence which converges to that point, and that there is no subsequence of your sequence which converges to a point outside of $C$ (excluding $\pm \infty$).

If I take an enumeration of $\mathbb{Q}$ that will have subsequences which converge everywhere in $\mathbb{R}$. I want to somehow cut out the portions of $\mathbb{Q}$ which are not near $C$. Initially I thought to just take $\mathbb{Q} \cap C$ but this didn't work. Perhaps I could modify this trick a little to get it to work? Or is there a better way to do it?

nullUser
  • 27,877
  • 3
    $C$ has to be bounded, or there will be a subsequence that converges to whichever of $\pm\infty$ is in the unbounded direction. – Ross Millikan Oct 21 '11 at 18:15
  • 2
    Are you sure of the "including $\pm\infty$" part? If $\infty$ is considered a "point", then one would expect that this point should also be considered when determining whether $C$ is closed or not. And if so, either $C$ is bounded (in which case there can never be a subsequence converging to $\infty$ anyway), or $C$ contains $\infty$ (in which case it should be allowed as a limit point). – hmakholm left over Monica Oct 21 '11 at 18:28
  • 1
    By the way, you also have to require that $C$ is non-empty. Otherwise there are no sequences at all. :-) – hmakholm left over Monica Oct 21 '11 at 18:33
  • No we don't need that it is nonempty, if it is empty then take the empty sequence and the statement is vacuously true. – nullUser Oct 21 '11 at 18:47
  • 2
    A sequence is a function with domain $\mathbb{N}$. There's no such thing as an empty sequence. – Chris Eagle Oct 21 '11 at 19:23
  • Yes you are correct, I should be more careful when throwing around terms like "empty sequence". – nullUser Oct 21 '11 at 20:42
  • @Henning: We have here a case of two wrongs making a right. If $C$ is the empty set, then all sequences $S$ have the property that for every point $x \in C$, $S$ has a subsequence converging to $x$. This is vacuously true, because $C$ has no points. However, the fact remains that every sequence has a limit point in $\mathbb R \cup {-\infty,+\infty}$, so $C = \emptyset$ is debarred for this reason $-$ not because "there are no sequences at all". – TonyK Oct 21 '11 at 22:12
  • @Tony, both reasons work independently. It's like asking, "find a negative prime that is a perfect square". You can either say "that's impossible because there are no negative primes", or "that's impossible because no prime is a perfect square", and both of these would be right. However, you cannot (meaningfully) say, "it is impossible all right, but not because there are no negative primes". – hmakholm left over Monica Oct 21 '11 at 22:26
  • @Henning: But you can A say "All negative primes are perfect squares"! Just as you can say "If $C$ is empty, then all points in $C$ are accumulation points of every sequence." Both statements are (vacuously) true. So if asked to find a sequence, as in the OP, I choose (say) $a_n = 0$ for all $n$. This fails, not because $C$ contains a point that is not an accumulation point of $(a_n)$, but because $(a_n)$ has an accumulation point that is not in $C$. – TonyK Oct 22 '11 at 07:11
  • @Tony: I agree that all negative primes are perfect squares. My point is that this fact does not help you find a negative prime that is a perfect square. – hmakholm left over Monica Oct 22 '11 at 12:43
  • @Henning: You're still not getting it. If $C$ is empty, then given the instruction "find a sequence such that for every point in $C$ there is a subsequence of your sequence which converges to that point", I reply with my sequence $(a_n) = (0,0,0,...)$. What don't you understand about this? – TonyK Oct 22 '11 at 14:02
  • @Tony: Your sequence $(a_n)=(0,0,0,\ldots)$ does not qualify because it is not a sequence of elements from $C$. It doesn't count, no matter what its limits are or aren't. (Wait... are sequences with elements outside $C$ actually allowed? The question now seems to be ambiguous on that point, never specifying what kind of things the requested sequence is a sequence of). – hmakholm left over Monica Oct 22 '11 at 15:11
  • Well, I'm glad we got that sorted out :-) – TonyK Oct 22 '11 at 15:20

3 Answers3

3

I think this requires (countable) choice in general. Enumerate all open intervals with rational endpoints, and for each such interval $I$ choose a point in $I\cap C$ if one exists (and throw away the interval otherwise). The set of all the chosen points will be dense in $C$.

2

This might be easier: Let $\{x_{1},\;x_{2},\; x_{3},\;...\}$ be a countable dense subset of $C$ and let the sequence be

$$x_{1},\; x_{1},\; x_{2},\;x_{1},\;x_{2},\;x_{3},\;x_{1},\;x_{2},\;x_{3},\;x_{4},\;...$$

There are some details to fill in (what if the set is finite, how do we know that no subsequences converge to a point not in $C$, etc.), which I'll leave to you.

  • Exactly my question, it is not clear at all that an arbitrary closed set has a countable dense subset. – nullUser Oct 21 '11 at 18:25
  • @Kb100: You may want roughly indicate the mathematical level that is being assumed, as I took it for granted that we could use the fact that $\mathbb R$ is separable. In fact, I'm using the fact that $\mathbb R$ is hereditarily separable, which is equivalent to separability in metric spaces. – Dave L. Renfro Oct 21 '11 at 18:31
  • I have no idea what that even means =. This is introductory real analysis. – nullUser Oct 21 '11 at 18:35
  • @Kb100: Unless I'm overlooking something, I think you have enough if you use Henning Makholm's answer along with mine. However, it would probably be a good idea to try to prove the result for some specific closed sets, such as $[0,1]$ and ${\frac{1}{n}:;n=1,2,3,...} \cup {0},$ to get a better feel for what's going on. – Dave L. Renfro Oct 21 '11 at 20:12
  • Yes his idea was sufficient. I made some preferential changes to the idea but it was rather easy to prove with this bit of help. The general proof was less than a page. Thanks so much everyone! – nullUser Oct 21 '11 at 21:20
2

Here is an explicit construction.

For every $n\geqslant0$ call $I(n)$ the integer interval $I(n)=[2\cdot4^{n},8\cdot4^{n}-1]$. For every $k$ in $I(n)$, let $a(k)=2^{-n}(k-5\cdot4^{n})$, and $x(k)$ any point in $C$ such that $|x(k)-a(k)|=\min\{|x-a(k)|\mid x\in C\}$. Then $\mathfrak X=(x(k))_{k\geqslant2}$ is a sequence of elements of $C$ whose limit set is $C\cup D$ where $D\subseteq\{-\infty,+\infty\}$ is such that $D$ contains $-\infty$ if and only if $\inf C=-\infty$ and $D$ contains $+\infty$ if and only if $\sup C=+\infty$.

To see this, first note that every $x$ in $C$ is such that $|x|\leqslant3\cdot2^n$ for $n$ large enough. For every such $n$, there exists $k$ in $I(n)$ such that $|x-a(k)|\leqslant2^{-n-1}$. Since $|x(k)-a(k)|\leqslant2^{-n-1}$, $|x-x(k)|\leqslant2^{-n}$ hence $x$ is a limit point of $\mathfrak X$.

Finally, $\mathfrak X\subseteq C$ hence every limit point of $\mathfrak X$ is in the closure of $C$ in $\overline{\mathbb R}$, that is, in $C\cup D$.

Did
  • 279,727