$ \newcommand{\N}{\mathbb{N}} \newcommand{\Q}{\mathbb{Q}} \newcommand{\R}{\mathbb{R}} $ I thought I understood AC (axiom of choice), but I am now totally confused through some discussions.
Let me examine whether each of the following examples needs AC. Assume ZF.
Choose $ x \in (0, 1) $.
AC is unnecessary. (One existential quantification over an interval.)Let $ n \in \N $. Choose $ x \in (0,1)^n $.
AC is unnecessary because $x$ can be chosen by finite existential quantification.Let $ A = \{[a, b]| a,b \in \R,~a\le b\} $. There is a function $f:A \to \R$ such that $ f(I) \in I$ for all $ I \in A$.
AC is unnecessary because we can declare a choice function $c: A \to \R$ defined by $ c(I) = \min I \in I $ for all $I \in A$ though $A$ is infinite.Let $ A = \{(a, b)| a,b \in \R,~a < b\} $. There is a function $f:A \to \R$ such that $ f(I) \in I$ for all $ I \in A$.
AC is necessary because there is no finite quantification over $ A $ that specifies the choice of $x$.Let $ A = \{[a, b] \cap \Q| a,b \in \R,~a < b\} $ and $ B = \{(a, b) \cap \Q| a,b \in \R,~a < b\} $. Either there is a function $f:A \to \R$ such that $ f(I) \in I$ for all $ I \in A$ or there is a function $f:B \to \R$ ....
AC is necessary by the same reasoning in 4.Let $ A = \{ (a,b)|a,b \in \Q,~a < b \} $. There is a function $f:A \to \R$ such that $ f(I) \in I$ for all $ I \in A$.
AC is necessary by the same reasoning in 4 though $A$ is countable. I considered this example from the discussion by Karagila, which seems to be inconsistent with what I learned. Does countability assume some important role here?
Would you figure out what I am missing about the notion of AC?
Edit:
I think I overlooked some simple factors in making examples. :) I would like to add one more example:
- Let $A \subseteq P(\R)$. There is a function $f:A \to \R$ such that $ f(I) \in I$ for all $ I \in A$.
Then, is 7. the only case AC actually needed?