0

This may be too basic and am just missing a big fundamental block in probability. Suppose there are 4 people in a family. Each one gets picked randomly everyday for doing dishes. Let's say one of them is Bill.

Observer 1:

He starts predicting from day one. Let B=1 be Bill getting picked up and 0 otherwise.

Day 1:

$p(B_1=0) = \dfrac{3}{4}$

Day 2 (and day 1):

$p(B_2=0, B_1=0) = \dfrac{3}{4}\dfrac{3}{4}$

Day n (and earlier days):

$p(B_n=0, B_{n-1}=0, \cdots ,B_1=0) = \Big(\dfrac{3}{4}\Big)^n \tag{1}$

Observer 2:

He just pops up on nth day and predicts the event. According to him then,

$p(B_1=0) = \Big(\dfrac{3}{4}\Big) \tag{2}$

where, for observer 2 its the first day, which was nth day for observer 1. The events are random every day. They are neither in any way depend on observer 1 or 2 , or to one another (that is, event happening on day k is independent of day (k-1)).

So both observers are right in their own way. Then, what is the correct probability for that day, for Bill not getting picked up? Or which is better and why?

  • 1
    Observer $1$ needs to review basic probability! The probability that Bill is picked on day $2$ is not $(3/4)(3/4)$. That would be the probability of Bill being picked on both days 1 and 2. – Mike Earnest Aug 20 '18 at 18:53
  • very sorry, there was a mistake. – Parthiban Rajendran Aug 20 '18 at 18:56
  • Consider a point in time when Observer 1 has already been watching for $n-1$ days, and has seen someone else (not Bill) be picked on day $n - 1,$ and it has not yet been decided who will do the dishes on day $n$; suppose at that instant in time I ask Observer 1 to estimate the probability that Bill will be picked on day $n.$ What answer will Observer 1 give me? – David K Aug 20 '18 at 22:17

3 Answers3

2

It seems like the observers are actually answering a slightly different question than what you stated $B$ to be. For any given day, the probability that Bill isn't picked is always $\frac{3}{4}$. Observations of previous days do not matter.

It seems like the observers are answering this question: "Wow, Bill hasn't had to do the dishes at all! What is the probability of that happening?"

It makes perfect sense that the observers conclude different things. This is because they have different knowledge about what has happened. Let me try to make an analogy.

Let's say there is a geyser that very rarely erupts. On day, I see it erupt - a rare event. A minute later, my friend joins me and sees it erupt again - back to back eruptions are even more rare. My friend says "wow, that was a rare event we witnessed" and I say, "actually, it's rarer than you know!". There is difference because what we are referring to by "this event" are different. My friend is referring only to the eruption he saw, but I am referring to both eruptions.

In your example, Observer 1 has witness more things happening, so he concludes that the situation is more rare than Observer 2. To avoided this error, be careful about what exactly $B$ refers to. Try defining $B_i$ to be the probability that Bill is picked on day $i$ (and day $i$ only).

rikhavshah
  • 1,355
  • 1
    I have updated the notations. Can you please check and update now? yes both O1 and O2 are different, but in a sense, they both give a prediction what is probability of bill not getting picked that day? O1 fees less probability, and O2 feels higher with no prior info, so which one is more useful? For eg, if this is stock price, which one would you take for better prediction of stock that day? If so why? For eg, if O1, wouldnt it be a gambler's fallacy? – Parthiban Rajendran Aug 20 '18 at 19:48
  • Perfect! Your revisions look good. Now, on day $n$, the probability that O1 wants is not $P(B_1,B_2,\cdots, B_n)$. The reason for this, is that O1 already knows the outcome of $B_1,\cdots,B_{n-1}$! What O1 really wants is $P(B_1,B_2,\cdots, B_n ,|, B_1=1,\cdots,B_{n-1}=1)$. By Bayes rule, this is simply $P(B_n=1)=3/4$. – rikhavshah Aug 21 '18 at 00:11
  • To further clarify, it would be Gambler's fallacy: specifically, the fallacy is the belief that observing past events in any way effects the outcome of a current independent event. If you assume that the stock market randomly increases or decreases price every day, independently of previous days and external forces, then observations about days in the past tell you nothing about the price today. – rikhavshah Aug 21 '18 at 00:15
  • 1
    so, 1) you can never apply past joint probability when about to predict current event (assuming independence)? 2) when would past joint probability would be valid w.r.t time frames? only when they are dependent? – Parthiban Rajendran Aug 21 '18 at 06:37
  • I took the example from khan, here, where hypothesis is introduced. There Bill does not gets picked in a row, so khan calculates the probability what it would be and applies joint probability. According to us, then it is wrong?. At any day, his chance of not getting picked up is 3/4?! – Parthiban Rajendran Aug 21 '18 at 06:47
  • Correct; 2) Also correct. As for the Khan academy video, they are computing the probability of Bill getting or not getting picked for some days in a row without observing any of the days. Once you observe the first day, the probability that Bill won't get picked for the first three days changes. Khan is answering the question "What is the probability that this thing will happen on the first three days?" which is different from "What is the probability that this thing will happen on the first three days given that I saw what happened on the first two days already?"
  • – rikhavshah Aug 22 '18 at 17:17
  • thank you. Can you also please answer my other question here – Parthiban Rajendran Aug 22 '18 at 18:35
  • 1
    @PaariVendhan Why have you not given the check mark to this answer? It makes it look like you are still waiting for this question to be answered for you. – David K Sep 01 '18 at 17:37
  • sorry about that, missed it amid multiple questions. – Parthiban Rajendran Sep 03 '18 at 07:02