5

According to standard mathematics, the Natural Numbers are given. Moreover, they are given as a (completed) Infinite Set. This set is commonly denoted as: $$ \mathbb{N} = \left\{ 1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18,19,\, \dots \right\} $$ Theorem. The set of all natural numbers is a completed infinity.
Proof. A set is infinite (i.e. a completed infinity) if there exists a bijection between that set and a proper subset of itself. Now consider the even naturals. They are a proper subset of the naturals and a bijection can be defined between the former and the latter. The "numerosity" of the evens is equal to the "numerosity" of the naturals. There are "as many" evens as there are naturals. As follows:

  2  4  6  8 10 12 14 16 18 20 22 24 26 28 30 32 34 36 38 ...
  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |  |
  1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 ...
Galileo's Paradox. The cardinality of the squares equals the cardinality of the naturals. There are "as many" squares as there are naturals. Proof. There exists a bijection between the naturals and the squares. The numerosity of the squares equals the numerosity of the naturals:
1 2 3  4  5  6  7  8  9  10  11  12  13  ..
| | |  |  |  |  |  |  |   |   |   |   |
1 4 9 16 25 36 49 64 81 100 121 144 169  ..
The cardinality of the powers of $7$ equals the cardinality of the naturals. There are "as many" powers of $7$ as there are naturals. Proof. There exists a bijection between the naturals and these powers:
1  2   3    4     5      6      7       8        9        10  ..
|  |   |    |     |      |      |       |        |         | 
7 49 343 2401 16807 117649 823543 5764801 40353607 282475249  ..
In general. Let there be defined a function $\;A(n) : \mathbb{N} \rightarrow \mathbb{N}$ . Assume that $\,A(n)\,$ is a sequence which is monotonically increasing with $\;n\;$ . Then we have the following bijection:
   1     2     3     4     5     6    7     8     9   .. 
   |     |     |     |     |     |    |     |     |
 A(1)  A(2)  A(3)  A(4)  A(5)  A(6) A(7)  A(8)  A(9)  ..
It can be concluded that the cardinality of the set $\;\left\{n\in\mathbb{N}:A(n)\right\}\;$ is $\;\aleph_0\;$, which is the cardinality of the naturals. Examples are:

  • $A(n) = 2\cdot n\;$ (the even numbers)
  • $A(n) = n^2\;$ (Galileo's paradox)
  • $A(n) = 7^n\;$ (powers of seven)
But let's have a second thought about all this [ e.g with $A(n) = 7^n$ ]:
  1   2 3 4 5 6   7  8 9 10 .. 48  49  50 .. 343 .. 2401 ..
  0   0 0 0 0 0   1  1 1  1     1   2   2      3       4   : D(n)
A(0)            A(1)              A(2)       A(3)    A(4)
Let $D(n)$ be the number of $A(m)$ values (count) less than or equal to $n$, where $(m,n)$ are natural numbers. Then we have the following theorem, tentatively called the Inverse Function Rule: $$ \lim_{n\rightarrow \infty} \frac{D(n)}{ A^{-1}(n) } = 1 $$ Proof. $A(n)$ is monotonically increasing with $n$ , therefore the inverse sequence $A^{-1}(n)$ exists in the first place. And it is monotonically increasing as well. Furthermore, we see that $\,D(n)\,$ is $\,m\,$ for $\,A(m) \le n < A(m+1)$ .
Consequently: $\;A(D(n)) \le n < A(D(n)+1)\;$ , hence $\;D(n) \le A^{-1}(n) < D(n) + 1\;$ , therefore $\;A^{-1}(n) - 1 < D(n) \le A^{-1}(n)\;$ .
Divide by $\;A^{-1}(n)\;$ to get: $\;1 - 1/A^{-1}(n) < D(n) / A^{-1}(n) \le 1\;$ . For $\,n\rightarrow \infty\,$ now the theorem follows, because $\;A^{-1}(n) \rightarrow \infty\;$ . Written as an asymptotic equality: $\,D(n) \approx A^{-1}(n) $ .

Examples. Revealing the Double Think.

  • $A(n) = 2.n \;\Longrightarrow\;\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} D(n)/[\,n/2\,] = 1 \;\Longrightarrow\; D(n) \approx n/2$
    The numerosity of the evens is not equal but  half  the numerosity of the naturals
  • $A(n) = n^2 \;\Longrightarrow\;\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} D(n)/\sqrt{n} = 1\;\Longrightarrow\; D(n) \approx \sqrt{n}$
    The numerosity of the squares is the square root of the numerosity of the naturals
  • $A(n) = 7^n \;\Longrightarrow\;\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} D(n)/[\,\ln(n)/\ln(7)\,] = 1\;\Longrightarrow\; D(n) \approx \log_7(n)$
    The numerosity of the powers of 7 is the 7-logarithm of the numerosity of the naturals
Still another example at the Wikipedia page about Fibonacci numbers : For large $\,n$ , the Fibonacci numbers are approximately $F_n \approx \phi^n/\sqrt{5}$ . Giving a limit similar to the one for the powers of seven: $$ A(n) = F_n \quad\Longrightarrow\quad \lim_{n\rightarrow\infty} \frac{D(n)}{\ln(n.\sqrt{5}) / \ln( \phi )} = 1 \qquad \mbox{where} \quad \phi = \frac{1}{2}(1+\sqrt{5}) $$ Question. My problem is nomenclature in the first place. The term Inverse Function Rule seems to have been coined up somewhere on the internet but I could't find any application resemblant to the above - there also is a rumour that it goes all the way back to Carl Friedrich Gauss, but I coun't find any sensible reference confirming this.
Wouldn't even dare to ask about the more important thing, namely what is the "correct" way to no double think about numerosities: cardinalities or via the "inverse function rule" ?
Han de Bruijn
  • 17,070
  • 1
    Your $D(n)$ (or rather $\lim_{n\to\infty}\frac1n D(n)$) is called a density. The limit need not always exist. – Hagen von Eitzen May 02 '14 at 12:34
  • I have not heard the term "numerosity" before. Typically characterize the size of a set by its cardinality. – Alex G. May 02 '14 at 12:35
  • I haven't ever heard the phrase "completed infinity" before, but I see you've defined it as Dedekind infinite. A little more searching and I did find this wiki mentioning the term you used. No matter what term you use, it would really be a lot better if you defined the term before you used it in a theorem statement. – rschwieb May 02 '14 at 13:10
  • @AlexGrounds: "Numerosity" seems to be a common English word, with "numerousness" as one of its synonyms. But I'm not a native English speaker. Anyway, I needed a word somewhat less specific than cardinality and thought this would fit the bill. – Han de Bruijn May 03 '14 at 12:55
  • @HagenvonEitzen: Instead of e.g. the square counting function, let $D(n)$ be the prime counting function: $$ \lim_{n\to\infty} \frac{D(n)}{A^{-1}(n)} = 1 \qquad \mbox{where} \qquad A^{-1}(n) = \frac{n}{\ln(n)}$$ Does nobody notice that the (second, no cardinality) numerosity is analogous to this, a PNT look-alike, so to speak? – Han de Bruijn May 03 '14 at 12:58
  • 2
    This looks like the concept of natural density to me. – EuYu May 05 '14 at 08:06
  • The cardinality of instances of the word "cardinality" in this question is > 6. Someone more powerful than I nevertheless must have thought it's reasonable to remove the tag (cardinality), which was chosen carefully and on purpose by me. Why? – Han de Bruijn May 05 '14 at 13:30
  • @EuYu: Don't think so. With natural density, the numerosity of the squares turns out to be zero, which is not the case with the above theory. Again, what's the problem with a "square counting function" instead of the "prime counting function"? – Han de Bruijn May 05 '14 at 13:35
  • Han de Bruijn writes above: "I needed a word somewhat less specific than cardinality...". As a general rule, if you're trying to avoid words with specific meanings, then you're not doing mathematics. – WillO May 07 '14 at 19:29
  • 1
    @WillO: There are numerous ways to do mathematics :-) – Han de Bruijn May 09 '14 at 09:20
  • I will say that the fact that your concepts rely strongly and inherently on the fact that you're working with numbers, and performing arithmetic operations, is the first clue that 'cardinality' is not the concept you want here, since the cardinality of a set is - by its very conceptualization - independent of any structure on the members of the set. (This is arguably at some level what the axiom of replacement is about.) – Steven Stadnicki Sep 29 '15 at 22:28

2 Answers2

3

There are some stabs being made at expanding the idea of asymptotic densities and measure to account for our basic intuition that the whole should be greater than the part, even for infinite sets. Vieri Benci, Mauro DiNasso and Marco Forti, among others, are doing work along these lines.

A rather advanced treatment is here http://arxiv.org/abs/1011.2089

Recently, this nice, readable article made its way into press at the Journal of Logic and Analysis: Elementary Numerosity and Measure http://arxiv.org/pdf/1212.6201.pdf

3

If I understood the question correctly, the OP is asking for one of these:

  1. An established name for the "Inverse function rule" stated in the question
  2. An established name for a concept of "numerosity" based on that rule
  3. A resolution to the discrepancy between this concept and set theoretical cardinality.

1.

The expression $\lim_{n\rightarrow\infty}\tfrac{D(n)}{A^{-1}(n)}$ raises the question of how is $A^{-1}(n)$ defined for $n$ not in the image of $A$. The theorem seems to state that any extension of $A^{-1}$ to a monotone function on the reals is asymptotically equivalent to $D$. I am inclined to believe there's no established name for this result in the literature.

2.

I don't believe there's an established name for this either. While similar to natural density, the "numerosity" here is given not as a number, but as a function (or rather, an asymptotic equivalence class). There exist other examples of classifying objects by asymptotic behaviour, computational complexity being the main exponent.

3.

The answer would depend on what question is one trying to address by the concept.

Cardinality is the natural answer to the question "how many elements are there in a collection?", based on the idea that if you can put the elements of one collection in one-to-one correspondence with the elements of the other, the collections are the same size (the OP's own diagrams illustrate this quite well). This makes no allusion whatsoever to any properties of the elements, or their relation to one another—it only requires that enough elements exist on each side to match the other side. One can rearrange or relabel the elements of a set at will, and the cardinality will remain unchanged. Much of set theory is about the question of when and how can one construct such one-to-one correspondences, to the point where one can argue that the only really "interesting" property of a set is its cardinality (more precisely, the category of sets is equivalent to the category of cardinal numbers).

Both natural density and "numerosity", on the other hand, are different properties of the distribution of a subset of naturals within the whole, namely different ways to answer the question "how often does one encounter elements of this subset among the naturals?", likely to be of interest in probabilistic number theory. Both depend strongly on the order structure of the naturals—if we were to rearrange the naturals (and the elements of $A$ accordingly), both measures could vary wildly. Each measure corresponds to a different form of approximation of the relative frequency of finite prefixes of the naturals, one as a single number and the other as a curve. In the latter case, the fact that the distribution of a subset generated by a monotone function $A$ is approximated by the inverse function $A^{-1}$ seems akin to the relation between inverse functions and their derivatives.

askyle
  • 486
  • 1
    As a humble physicist by education, I'm inclined to say that there's not so much interesting with the fact that the evens, squares, prime numbers, Fibonacci numbers and powers of seven are countable. I find the Prime Number Theorem much more interesting than the cardinality of the primes, the latter being the bare fact that they are countable and that's it. – Han de Bruijn May 09 '14 at 09:23
  • Since a comment cannot be downvoted, I'm even inclined to propose formally (and ironically): cardinality of the naturals $= \aleph_0$ , hence it follows that: cardinality of the evens $= \aleph_0/2$ , cardinality of the squares $= \sqrt{\aleph_0}$ , cardinality of the powers of seven $= \log_7(\aleph_0)$ , and so on and so forth :-) – Han de Bruijn May 09 '14 at 09:32
  • 1
    On the other hand, it is remarkable to consider that the rationals and the algebraic numbers are countable, whereas the reals (and hence the irrationals and the transcendentals) are uncountable. Before Cantor, there were no known constructions of transcendental numbers, and people wondered whether there were any transcendentals at all. Cantor showed that such numbers must exist, simply because there are too many reals for all of them to be algebraic. – askyle May 09 '14 at 13:29