For $k \in \mathbb{N},\, k \geq 2$, define $S(k) := \operatorname{lcm}(2,\dots,k)$.
$S$ stands for "superprimorial", as it is a name I've seen come up once before and that I kinda like: it can be written as the (finite) product $S(k) = \prod_{p \in \mathbb{P}} p^{\max\{\alpha \in \mathbb{N} \,|\, p^\alpha \,\leq\, k\}} = \prod_{p \in \mathbb{P}} p^{\big\lfloor \frac{\ln(k)}{\ln(p)} \big\rfloor}$ where $\mathbb{P}$ is the set of positive prime numbers, and since the sequence of the exponents is decreasing when $p$ increases, it is a product of primorials, a "super" primorial so to speak.
Below are my two personal conjectures, based on manual realisation for smaller $k$ and a rudimentary Python program I made for bigger but still small $k$. I tried searching on this site among other $\operatorname{lcm}$ and number theory posts to see if this was answered or at least already talked about, to no avail. I'm rather new here though so maybe I missed some?
Conjectures:
- $(1)$ For $k \neq 8$, $S(k) + 1$ and $S(k) - 1$ are squarefree, i.e. for all $p \in \mathbb{P}$, $p^2$ does not divide $S(k) \pm 1 $.
- (EDIT: known to be false sadly) $(2)$ For all $k \geq 2$, $S(k) + 1$ and $S(k) - 1$ each have at most $\bigg\lfloor \frac{\ln(k)}{\ln(2)} \bigg\rfloor = \max\{\alpha \in \mathbb{N} \,|\, 2^\alpha \,\leq\, k\}$ prime divisors counted with multiplicity.
$(2)$ would imply, for example, that $S(2^{100}) + 1$, which is a pretty big number, would have at most $100$ prime divisors, which, while not that small for the purpose of finding prime candidates, is still really small. Plus, the fact that this concerns both $S(k) + 1$ AND $S(k) - 1$ could potentially lead towards the twin prime conjecture or something...?
$k = 8$ stands out since $S(8) + 1 = 841 = 29^2$ is not squarefree, and of course if $(1)$ holds then there's no need of talking about multiplicity in $(2)$ for $k \neq 8$. Do note that $(1)$ and $(2)$ still remain independent questions though, as in, unless the proof of either of them proves the other one, $(1)$ and $(2)$ should not imply each other (I don't think?).
Here are the questions I have in mind right now, having written those conjectures:
- A) The kinda obvious question: do we know those assertions to be true? Or any partial version, like "true for big enough $k$", "an infinity of $k$", and so forth...? If not, maybe there are counterexamples other than $k = 8$ that I missed, which is very possible?
- B) At the moment I'm not really knowledgeable on number theory proofs: any recommendations on results and/or techniques that might help me start? For $(2)$, I've tried upper bounding the number of divisors of $S(k) \pm 1$ by the number of numbers coprime to $S(k)$ ($S(k)$ being coprime to them, their divisors also have to be coprime to $S(k)$) due to the definition of $S(k)$ making it so that a "lot" of numbers are not coprime to $S(k)$ AND that it is "easy" to evaluate $\varphi(S(k))$ due to the multiplicativity of $\varphi$ (Euler's totient function for those unaware), and I've thought of removing the numbers between $S(k)$ and $S(k)/k$ since all of them are guaranteed to not be "divisor candidates", but besides that I'm sort of at a loss. As for $(1)$, I'm aware of the existence of the Möbius function and the fact there are quite a few results involving it, but I don't really know if that'll really help considering the challenge of the "$\pm 1$"...
(Hopefully my English is correct enough. Any advice on the form of the post itself is also welcome.)
EDIT: It would seem that conjecture $(2)$ is false by looking at $S(359) - 1$ which has $10$ prime factors (thanks a lot Peter)! Yet, it could still be interesting to know if such counterexamples are rare, or if a different upper bound could still apply, and so on, so I'll leave conjecture $(2)$'s false statement on the post.