EDIT: As per the comments, both are equivalent. I searched the top-voted questions under the tag [induction] but couldn’t find a Proof of the Second Principle, assuming the First Principle. The reverse (First from Second) is pretty easy, so I’d like to see a proof of Second from First.
I’m going through the first chapter (“Preliminaries”) of David M. Burton’s Elementary Number Theory, 7th Ed.
The First Principle of Finite Induction states that
Let S be a set of positive integers with the following properties:
(i) The integer $1$ belongs to S,
(ii) Whenever the integer $k$ is in S, the next integer $k+1$ must also be in S.
Then S is the set of all positive integers.
The Second Principle of Finite Induction states that
Let S be a set of positive integers with the following properties:
(i) The integer $1$ belongs to S,
(ii) Whenever the integers $1,2,…,k$ belong to S, the next integer $k+1$ must also be in S.
Then S is the set of all positive integers.
The author goes on to elaborate that both theorems can be generalised to start from any positive integer $n_0$ and shows us an example where the Second Principle (which is also called Strong Induction) is handier than the First:
Prove that for the nth term of the Lucas sequence $L_n$, $L_n< \left(\dfrac74\right)^n$.
Now my question is: Is there any technical reason (apart from “assuming all of $1,2,…,k$ is unnecessary when we can make do with only assuming $k$“) that the First Principle is preferred over the Second while doing things like:
Prove that $1+2+3+…+n=\dfrac{n(n+1)}{2}$ .
In other words, is the First Principle of Finite Induction essentially made redundant by the Second?