Chris Eagle’s answer is absolutely correct, but I think there’s a different, valuable way of looking at this. Specifically, I think this is best viewed as a special case of a more general tool. I’ll write it up as a separate answer.
To fix a little terminology and notation, let a “class” denote any collection of sets, and let $V$ denote the class of all sets. I am assuming you’re already familiar with the formal reasons that $V$ is not a set.
There are loads of different sufficient conditions for showing that a class is not a set. Here’s one of my favorites:
Theorem: Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a class. If for all sets $S \in V$, there is a an element $C \in \mathcal{C}$ such that $S \in C$, then $\mathcal{C}$ is not a set.
Proof: To prove this theorem, recall the axiom of union, which says:
$$\forall F \exists A \forall Y \forall x \big [(x \in Y \wedge Y \in F) \rightarrow x \in A \big ] $$
Suppose that $\mathcal{C}$ is a set. Then we may apply this axiom to $\mathcal{C}$ and find that there is a set $A$ such that for all sets $Y \in \mathcal{C}$ and all $x \in Y$, we have that $x \in A$. By our condition on $\mathcal{C}$, we know that for every set $S$, there is a $C \in \mathcal{C}$ such that $S \in C$. It follows that for every set $S$, we have that $S \in A$. Thus $V \subseteq A$.
Additionally, we have that $A$ is a set, so we have that $A$ is a set containing all sets. Since the formula $x=x$ picks out all sets, it follows by restricted comprehension that $\{x \in A : x = x\} = V$ is a set. But there is no set of all sets. Thus $\mathcal{C}$ could not have been a set to begin with. □
This is a quite “general test” for checking if a class is not a set. We may easily apply it to your example.
Corollary: For $n > 0$, let $F_n$ denote the class of sets with exactly $n$ elements. $F_n$ is not a set.
Proof: There are $n$ distinct sets. Thus for any set $S$, there is a set $T$ such that $S \in T$ and $T$ has exactly $n$ elements. Thus we meet the hypotheses of the theorem. □