Let $\mu: \mathcal{P}(\mathbb{Z}) \rightarrow [0,1]$ be a finitely additive $\mathbb{Z}$-invariant probability measure on $\mathbb{Z}$. Such measures exist because $\mathbb{Z}$ is amenable and one can indeed describe examples of such measures as ultralimits of sequences of asymptotic densities computed with respect to a Følner sequence; for example, see here and here.
I have two questions which I hope are elementary, but I was not able to figure out.
- Does $\mu$ have to generalize the notion of asymptotic density of a subset of integers? In other words, does $\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \frac{|A \cap [-n,n]|}{2n+1}=r$ imply that $\mu(A)=r$? The answer is clearly yes for infinite arithmetic progressions by finite additivity of $\mu$. On the other hand, sets of integers with asymptotic density can look very different than such sets, so I do not see how to extend the result to these sets.
- $\mu$ is necessarily not continuous from above or below; otherwise it would be a $\sigma$-additive measure as shown, for example, here. Indeed, we have that $\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \mu(\mathbb{Z}-[-n,n]) = 1 \neq 0 = \mu\left(\bigcap_{n \in \mathbb{N}} \mathbb{Z}-[-n,n]\right)$. My question this time is a bit vague. Is it possible to give a (useful) sufficient condition for a class of subsets of $\mathbb{Z}$ that guarantees the continuity of $\mu$ from above and below for sequences in this class? This would allow us to compute the probability of infinitely many events happening simultaneously in certain cases.
Perhaps I should mention the motivation behind this question. It is often written that "there is no way to choose an integer at random" due to the lack of a $\sigma$-additive measure on $\mathbb{Z}$ which chooses each integer with equal probability. But there are finitely additive such measures. So why don't we use these measures to model the situations where we need to choose an integer at random? If we are to do that, such measures need to satisfy certain intuitive properties; for example, it needs to generalize asymptotic density (hence my first question) and it should satisfy some basic identities that allow us to play with it (hence my second question).
Some more motivation: Let me also add how I ended up thinking about this in the first place. It is well-known that the probability that two randomly chosen integers from $\{1,2,\dots,n\}$ are coprime goes to $6/\pi^2$ as $n \rightarrow \infty$. Let us try formalize the idea given in this Wikipedia article using such a measure $\mu$ on $\mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}$ and try to exactly prove that "two randomly chosen integers are coprime with probability $6/\pi^2$."
Let $\mu: \mathcal{P}(\mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}) \rightarrow [0,1]$ be a finitely additive $\mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}$-variant probability measure. For each prime $p$, set $A_p=\{(m,n) \in \mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}: p \nmid a \text{ or } p \nmid b\}$. Then, finite additivity implies that $\mu(A_p)=1-\frac{1}{p^2}$ for any prime $p$. It follows that
$$\mu(\{(m,n) \in \mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}: gcd(m,n)=1\})=\mu\left(\bigcap_{p \text{ prime}} A_p\right) \leq \prod_{p \text{ prime}} \mu(A_p)=\frac{6}{\pi^2}$$
The lack of continuity of $\mu$ from above prevents us to conclude equality as it may be that $\prod_{p \text{ prime}} \mu(A_p)=\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty}\mu(A_2 \cap A_3 \cap \dots \cap A_{p_n}) \neq \mu\left(\bigcap_{p \text{ prime}} A_p\right)$. This is partly why I am interested in the second question; I'd be happy to see if this were actually equality, which, we know in our hearts, must be true!
Clearly the specific problem here regarding coprimality is just a distraction. What I really want to see is if "taking limits of probabilities obtained on the set $\{1,2,\dots,n\}$" actually corresponds to something meaningful in this finitely additive setting.