For completeness I’ll add an answer showing that in fact $\Bbb R$ can be partitioned into $\kappa$ sets closed under addition for any non-zero cardinal $\kappa\le 2^\omega=\mathfrak{c}$. (Of course this uses the axiom of choice.) Start with a Hamel basis $B=\{b_\xi:\xi<2^\omega\}$ for $\Bbb R$ over $\Bbb Q$. For each $x\in\Bbb R\setminus\{0\}$ there is a unique finite $B_x\subseteq B$ such that $x$ is a linear combination with non-zero rational coefficients of the members of $B_x$; let $B_x^+$ be the set of members of $B_x$ whose coefficients in that linear combination are positive. For each $\eta<2^\omega$ let
$$A_\eta=\big\{x\in\Bbb R:\min\{\xi<2^\omega:b_\xi\in B_x\}=\eta\text{ and }b_\eta\in B_x^+\big\}\,;$$
$b_\eta\in A_\eta$, so $A_\eta\ne\varnothing$, and $A_\eta$ is clearly closed under addition.
Now let $\kappa\le 2^\omega$ be a cardinal, and let $$D=\Bbb R\setminus\bigcup_{\xi<\kappa}A_\xi\,.$$
Clearly $\{D\}\cup\{A_\xi:\xi<\kappa\}$ is a partition of $\Bbb R$ into $\kappa$ parts if $\kappa\ge\omega$, and into $\kappa+1$ parts if $\kappa<\omega$, and it only remains to show that $D$ is closed under addition. But $x\in D$ iff either
- $\min\{\xi<2^\omega:b_\xi\in B_x\}\ge\kappa$, or
- $\eta=\min\{\xi<2^\omega:b_\xi\in B_x\}<\kappa$ and $b_\eta\notin B_x^+$, or
- $x=0$,
and it’s easy to check that the set of real numbers satisfying one of these conditions is closed under addition.