There's a famous proof that $\sqrt{2}$ is irrational by assuming $\sqrt{2}=p/q$ for relatively prime $p$ and $q$ and then proving that this leads to $p$ and $q$ being both even which contradicts with them being coprime.
Now there's something I noticed that may make another easier proof:
Assume for the sake of contradiction that there exists positive integers $p$ and $q$ such that $\gcd(p,q)=1 \implies \gcd(p^2,q^2)=1$, and $$\sqrt{2}=\frac{p}{q} \implies 2q^2=p^2 \implies q^2|p^2$$ Now the last result contradicts with $p^2$ and $q^2$ being coprime, except if $q^2=1 \implies q= 1 \implies p^2=2$, but $2$ is not a perfect square so there's no such $p$
Is this proof correct?
Edit (adding a comment): this can be generalized that for any positive integer $n>1$, the $n$th root of a non-$n$th-powered integer is irrational.
For example: let $k\ne m^n$ be a positive integer for any positive integer $m$, we have $\sqrt[n]{k}$ is irrational, because assume for the sake of contradiction (for coprime positive integers $p,q$, we have $\gcd(p,q)=1 \implies \gcd(p^n,q^n)=1$ because $p$ and $q$ have different prime factors and thus so is $p^n$ and $q^n$, considering the fundamental theorem of arithmetic) $$\sqrt[n]{k}=p/q \implies kq^n=p^n \implies q^n|p^n$$ this, similarly, contradicts with $\gcd(p^n,q^n)=1$ and implies $q^n=1$ and so $q=1$ so $k=p^n$, a contradiction.