2

Definition

The quasi-component $Q_x$ of $x\in X$ is the intersection of the clopen set that contains $x$.

Observation

Since the intersection (infinite as well) of closed sets is always closed, any quasi-component is a closed set.

Lemma

The quasi-components of two distinct points of a topological space $X$ either coincide or are disjoint, so that all quasi-components constitute a decomposition of the space $X$ into pairwise disjoint closed subsets.

Proof. So if $y\in Q_x$ for some $x,y\in Q_x$ then clearly $Q_y\subseteq Q_x$ and so this means that if $Q$ is clopen and $x\in Q$ then $y\in Q$. So now we suppose that $Q_y\subset Q_x$, that is there exist a clopen set $Q$ such that $Q\subseteq X\setminus\{x\}$ and so $X\setminus Q$ is a clopen such that $x\in X\setminus Q$ and so $y\in X\setminus Q$, but this would mean that $Q\cap X\setminus Q\neq\varnothing$ and clearly this is impossible.

Corollary

For any topological space $X$ the relation $$ x\approx y\iff Q_x=Q_y $$ for any $x,y\in X$ is an equivalence relation in $X$.

Corollary

For any topological space $X$ and for any $x,y\in X$ it follows that $x\approx y$ iff for any binary open partition of $X$ it follows that $x$ and $y$ belong to the same part.

Proof. If $x\approx y$ clearly then if there exist a binary partition of $X$ such that $x$ and $y$ don't belong to the same part then there exist two disjoint open set $U$ and $V$ such that $x\in U$ and $y\in V$ and $U\cap V=\varnothing$; but if this was happen then $U$ and $V$ are two clopen set such that $x\in U$ and $y\in V$ and $x\notin V$ and $y\notin U$ and this would be inconsistence respect to the assumption $x\approx y$. Now we observe that if $Q\subseteq X$ is clopen then $Q$ and $X\setminus Q$ induce a open partition on $X$. So if $x,y\in X$ are such that for any binary partition of $X$ it follows that $x$ and $y$ belong to the same part then if $Q$ is a clopen set and $x\in Q$ then $y\in Q$ and so clearly $Q_x=Q_y$.

Now what shown below is a theorem of "Topology II" by Kazimierz Kuratowski

enter image description here

So I don't understand the point $2$ of the proof and so to explain it I proved the second corollary: so is its proof correct? then using it could I explain the point 2? Then I don't understand why $\mathfrak{z\approx m}\in(\mathfrak{z^1,...,z^n})\times\mathscr{X}_n$ and $\mathfrak{m\approx y}\in\mathscr{X_1\times...\times X_n}\times\mathfrak{y}^n$. Then why $\mathfrak{z\approx m}\in\Big((\mathfrak{z^1,...,z}^{(n-1)})\times\mathscr{X_n}\Big)\cup\Big(\mathscr{X_1\times...\times X}_{n-1}\times(\mathfrak{y}^n)\Big)$ and so why $\mathfrak{z\approx m}$ in $\mathscr{X_1\times...\times X}_n$? So if this is true why $\mathfrak{z\approx y}$ in $\mathscr{X_1\times...\times X}_n$? Finally why if $(\mathfrak{z}^{t_1},...\mathfrak{z}^{t_n})\approx(\mathfrak{y}^{t_1},...,\mathfrak{y}^{t_n})$ in $\mathscr{X_{t_1}\times....\times X_{t_n}}$ then $\mathfrak{m\approx y}$ in $\mathscr{R}$ and so then why in $\mathscr{X}$?

So could someone help me, please?

Henno Brandsma
  • 242,131
  • I’m not sure what you mean by point $2$. – Brian M. Scott Apr 24 '20 at 21:47
  • @BrianM.Scott The point 2 is $$\mathfrak{G\cap H}=\varnothing, \mathcal{G\cup H}=\mathscr{X}, \mathfrak{z\in G}, \mathfrak{y\in H}$$ So could you answer the question, please? I'm sure you know the answer. I thought about what I don't understand, but unfortunately I didn't found an answer. – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 07:39
  • weird to see it in English, I have the French edition. – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 09:01
  • 1
    The point $(2)$ is to see the left to right implication of $(1)$. If two points are equivalent but in some coordinate $x_t \not\approx y_t$ ,we separate them by $G_t$ and $H_t$ and then $\pi_t^{-1}[G_t]$ and $\pi_t^{-1}[H_t]$ form a separation between them in the product, contradiction. That's all he's saying. – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 09:53
  • Unfortunately I see that I did a grave mistake: the point 2 is not what I indicated but is $G_t\cap H_t=\varnothing,\quad G_t\cup H_t=\mathscr{X}_t,\quad\mathfrak{z}^t\in G_t,\quad\mathfrak{y}^t\in H_t$. So I ask if using the second corollary I can explain what I indicated now. Forgive my confusion – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 13:23
  • @HennoBrandsma If you like the English edition of Kuratowski's book you can download it here. Anyway could you answer the question? I'm sure you know the answer. – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 13:26
  • I have it on paper (bought it in Paris a long time ago). Engelking, Kelley, etc too. 4 shelves of topology. I already answered, didn’t you see? – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 13:43

1 Answers1

1

The connection between $Q_x$ and $\approx$, i.e.

$$Q_x = Q_y \iff x \approx y\tag{a}$$

I would show as follows: suppose $x \approx y$. Then let $z \in Q_x$; we want $z \in Q_y$, so let $C$ be any clopen of $X$ that contains $y$. As $C,C^\complement$ partitions $X$, and $x \approx y$, we get $x \in C$. So $z \in Q_x \subseteq C$, so $z \in C$; as $C$ was arbitrary, $z \in Q_y$. So $Q_x \subseteq Q_y$, and by a symmetrical argument (interchange $x$ and $y$) we get $Q_y \subseteq Q_x$ and the left hand side of $(a)$ has been shown. Now suppose $Q_x=Q_y$, and let $U,V$ be a (cl)open partition of $X$ with $x \in U$ (say). As $y \in Q_y = Q_x \subseteq U$, $y \in U$ as well, and as the partition was arbitrary, $x \approx y$.


As to productivity of $\approx$, we want to show in $X=\prod_{j \in J} X_j$ that

$$x=(x_j)_j \approx y=(y_j)_j \iff \forall j \in J: x_j \approx y_j\tag{1}$$

The point $(2)$ is to see the left to right implication of $(1)$. If two points are equivalent but in some coordinate $x_j \not\approx y_j$ ,we can separate them by a (cl)open partition $G_j, H_j$ of $X_j$ and then $\pi_j^{-1}[G_j]$ and $\pi_j^{-1}[H_j]$ form a (cl)open separation between them in the product, contradiction. That's all he's saying there; It's also the general argument that $$Q_x \subseteq \prod_j Q_{x_j}$$

as it were.

The finite case hinges on the case $n=2$ really: if $x_1 \approx x_2$ in $X$ and $y_1 \approx y_2$ in $Y$, the claim is that $(x_1,x_2) \approx (y_1,y_2)$ in $X \times Y$ (and then induction implies the finite product equality case).

Kuratowski uses that $\{x_1\} \times Y \simeq Y$ (homeomorphism via projection) and $X \times \{y_2\} \simeq X$ as well, and $(x_1,y_2)$ is their "link": if $C_1, C_2$ is a binary clopen partition of $X \times Y$, their intersection with $X \times \{y_2\}$ is one too, and this contains both $(x_1,y_2)$ and $(x_2,y_2)$ and as $x_1 \approx x_2$ and these correspond under the homeomorphism, we see that $(x_1, y_2)$ and $(x_2,y_2)$ are in the same clopen set, say $C_1$ for definiteness.

Similarly $y_1 \approx y_2$ in $Y$ so in the homeomorphic space $\{x_1\} \times Y$ we know that $(x_1, y_1)$ and $(x_1, y_2)$ are in the same clopen set (in the partition of $C_1,C_2$ intersected with $\{x_1\} \times Y$) and we already know the $(x_1,y_2)$ is in $C_1$ so $(x_1,y_1)$ is too. In conclusion, $(x_1,y_1)$ and $(x_2,y_2)$ are both in $C_1$, and as the partition was arbitrary, $(x_1,y_1) \approx (x_2,y_2)$.

So in the finite case (by obvious induction, using $(X_1 \times \ldots X_{n_1}) \times X_n \simeq X_1 \times \ldots X_{n-1} \times X_n$, etc.)

$$(x_1,\ldots, x_n) \approx (y_1, \ldots,y_n) \iff \forall 1 \le i \le n: x_1 \approx y_i$$

Note the similarity with the usual proof of connectedness of finitely many connected spaces, using a glueing argument.

The general case uses the "finiteness" of product open basis sets in a similar way: we assume that $\forall j \in J: x_j \approx y_j$ and want to show $x=(x_j)_j \approx (y_j)_j=y$ (in modern notation). So let $G,H$ be a binary clopen partition of $X =\prod_j X_j$ and say $x \in G$. We can find a finite set of indices $F \subseteq J$ such that $O= \prod_j O_j$ obeys that $O_j = X_j$ for $j \notin F$ and all $O_j$ are open in $X_j$ and $$x \in O \subseteq G$$

Then Kuratowski forms the auxiliary point $(w=(w_j)_j$ defined by

$$w_j=\begin{cases} x_j & j \in F\\ y_j &j \notin F\end{cases}$$

and note that $w \in O$ so $w \in G$.

Also $X_F:=\prod_{j \in J} Y_j \subseteq X$, with $Y_j= X_j, j \in F$, $Y_j=\{y_j\}, j \notin F$, is homeomorphic to $\prod_{j \in F} X_j$, a finite product and contains $w$ and $y$, with $\pi_F$ as a homeomorphism, and $x_j \approx y_j$ for $j \in F$ in particular, the finite case we just showed then implies that $(x_j)_{j \in F} \approx (y_j)_{j \in F}$ too, so their homeomorphic images $w \approx y$ in $X_F$, so $y \in G$ too (using the induced partition of $G \cap X_F,H \cap X_F$ again). Hence $x \approx y$ and we're done.

Henno Brandsma
  • 242,131
  • Okay, however I don't understand exactly which function is $\pi_F$; roughly it seems to me that $\pi_F: X_F\rightarrow \prod_{j\in F} X_j$ and $\pi_F(x):=x(j)$ for any $x\in X_F$ and $j\in F$, right? – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 14:04
  • @AntonioMariaDiMauro it’s not very relevant but just the projection from the whole product to the subproduct on $F$, which is a continuous open bijection on $X_F$. – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 14:06
  • @AntonioMariaDiMauro Do you get the argument now? Capisce? – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 14:22
  • Yes, I understand, that is capisco. Thanks too much for your explanation: grazie!!!! – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 15:23
  • de nada, or do you say de niente? @AntonioMariaDiMauro – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 15:24
  • I am italian so I say di niente; anyway I perfectly understand Spanish, since indeed the Italian and the Spanish are very similar. – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 15:30
  • @AntonioMariaDiMauro I did Latin in high school for 5 years. I derive Spanish and Italian and Catalan via complex sets of rules. Up to a point I can read all of these. French even better, as that was a separate subject for 6 years and I still read books in French regularly. – Henno Brandsma Apr 25 '20 at 15:55
  • I too studied Latin and even ancient Greek: I attended Gymnasium. Anyway I speak a latin language from I was child so to me understand Spanish or Portuguese or French would be quite simply even I was not study Latin: so when you say that you use a complex sets of rules to derive the romance language from latin then I image that for people don't speak Latin language as a child it is more difficult to learn one as to me is difficult to lear a german language. – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 16:36
  • Moreover I'm from South Italy so I too speak neapolitan that is a language highly influenced from Spanish language since the South Italy was ruled from Spanish people for some centuries; then my town was founded from ancient greek people so some words are greek words, as else many words of italian language – Antonio Maria Di Mauro Apr 25 '20 at 16:36