11

I've been pondering the following question.

How can we measure the amount of "space" above an element $p$ in a partially ordered set $P$?

One way would be to try to cram the elements of increasingly large ordinals into the space above $p$, respecting order. The least ordinal whose elements "don't fit" is then a measure of the amount of space above $p$ in $P$.

This suggests the following definition. (Recall that an order monomorphism preserves strict order relationships).

Definition. Given a partially ordered set $P$ and an element $p \in P$, the cramming ordinal of $p$ is the least ordinal $\alpha$ such that there is no order monomorphism $f : \alpha \rightarrow P$ satisfying $f(0)=p$.

This begs the following question.

What is the cramming ordinal of the element $0 \in \mathbb{R}$?

(Actually, I presume all elements of $\mathbb{R}$ have the same cramming ordinal in $\mathbb{R}$, but lets just consider $0$ for concreteness).

Now observe that $\omega$ is a lower bound for the cramming ordinal of $0$, because $f$ is witnessed by the identity function.

Observe also that given a monomorphism $f : \alpha \rightarrow \mathbb{R}$ satisfying $f(0)=0$, it holds that $\tan^{-1} \circ f$ is also a monomorphism. However, the range of $\tan^{-1} \circ f$ is bounded above in $\mathbb{R}$. So we can copy the idea of $\tan^{-1} \circ f$ repeatedly, in fact $\omega$ many times. So if $\alpha$ is a lower bound for the cramming ordinal of $0$, then $\alpha \omega$ is a lower bound, too.

Thus since $\omega$ is a lower bound for the cramming ordinal of $0$, so too are $\omega^2$, $\omega^3$ etc.

My question is, what is the cramming ordinal of $0 \in \mathbb{R}$?

goblin GONE
  • 67,744

2 Answers2

13

First of all, the technical term is "cofinality of the cone generated by $p$", not "cramming ordinal of $p$".

Now, for the case of $\Bbb R$, note that the order is homogeneous, so the actual point we choose to "cram" above is irrelevant, but this also means that $0$ is as good as any.

More to the point, since the rationals are dense in $\Bbb R_+$, we can embed any countable into $\Bbb R_+$. This is proved by transfinite induction.

  • Clearly it's true for $0$;
  • If you can embed $\alpha$ using $f$, then without loss of generality you can embed it into $[0,1)$, then extend $f$ by setting $f(\alpha)=1$. This is clearly order preserving.
  • If $\beta$ is a limit ordinal and we can embed every smaller ordinal than $\beta$, write it as the union of intervals $[\alpha_i,\alpha_{i+1})$ each with order type strictly less than $\beta$ (e.g. take a strictly increasing sequence of ordinals, $\alpha_i$ with limit $\beta$).

    By the assumption we can embed every ordinal smaller than $\beta$, so we can embed the ordinal isomorphic to $[\alpha_i,\alpha_{i+1})$ into the interval $[i,i+1)$ in the rationals. Clearly we have embedded $\beta$ into the rationals by gluing the maps. $\square$

Furthermore if we do embed $\omega_1$, then we can cut $\Bbb R$ into $\aleph_1$ disjoint open intervals, this is impossible because there is an injection from every family of disjoint open intervals into $\Bbb Q$.

Therefore the cramming ordinal is $\omega_1$.

Asaf Karagila
  • 393,674
  • 1
    Why is it that we can embed any countable ordinal into $\mathbb R$ in a way that preserves order? – A.S Mar 31 '13 at 22:13
  • @Andrew: I added this to the answer. – Asaf Karagila Mar 31 '13 at 22:23
  • 1
    It's not immediately obvious that any countable limit ordinal is a $\omega$-indexed sum of strictly smaller ordinals. –  Mar 31 '13 at 22:24
  • @Hurkyl: Is it not? – Asaf Karagila Mar 31 '13 at 22:25
  • @Asaf: I could be having a brain lapse, or just have never learned a relevant piece of theory, but I'm not seeing it. –  Mar 31 '13 at 22:28
  • @Hurkyl: If not, there would be an infinite descending chain, contradicting the well ordering of the ordinal a. – Ross Millikan Mar 31 '13 at 22:31
  • 2
    @Hurkyl: Take $f$ a bijection of $\omega$ and $\alpha$, some countable limit ordinal. This bijection cannot have an infinite decreasing sequence, so for every $n$ there is some $k>n$ such that $f(n)<f(k)$. Since $f$ is a bijection this sequence must be cofinal in $\alpha$. – Asaf Karagila Mar 31 '13 at 22:38
  • 1
    @Asaf: Ah yes, it's much clearer when you come at it from that angle. –  Mar 31 '13 at 22:42
  • Nice answer. By the way, the fact that we can embed any countable ordinal into $\mathbb{R}$ is reflected by the fact that the construction of the long line uses the first uncountable ordinal. If you use any smaller ordinal, you just get the real line! – Jim Belk Mar 31 '13 at 22:44
  • @Jim: I'm not 100% clear as to why this argument is not circular. Why would you get the original line if you only have countably many copies, without using the fact that every countable ordinal can be embedded into $\Bbb R$ to begin with? – Asaf Karagila Mar 31 '13 at 22:46
  • @AsafKaragila My point is just that this fact is implicitly part of the motivation for the construction of the long line. I'm giving an application of your answer, not an alternative argument. – Jim Belk Mar 31 '13 at 23:06
  • @Jim: Ah, I see! :-) – Asaf Karagila Mar 31 '13 at 23:09
  • @Jim: In fact, it was that very fact that prevented me from fully latching onto some half-remembered idea that some $\varepsilon$ number was a counterexample to Asaf's claim. –  Mar 31 '13 at 23:34
  • @AsafKaragila, please see http://math.stackexchange.com/questions/347548/do-we-always-use-the-axiom-of-choice-when-picking-from-uncountable-number-of-set#comment747540_347548 – Will Jagy Apr 01 '13 at 01:04
  • 5
    But I like cramming ordinal of $p$: it has real style! – Brian M. Scott Apr 01 '13 at 01:35
  • I don't get how this relates to cofinality. By the cone generated by $p$, I presume you mean ${q \in P : q \geq p}.$ So the cone generated by $0 \in \mathbb{R}$ is $[0,\infty)$. Its cofinality is the least cardinality of a cofinal subset of $[0,\infty)$ which would just be $\aleph_0$. What am I missing here? – goblin GONE Dec 06 '14 at 10:57
  • @goblin: This also involves the homogeneity of $\Bbb R$, being order isomorphic to its non-trivial open intervals. If there was an embedding of $\omega_1$ into $\Bbb R$, we may assume that it was unbounded (by the homogeneity) and by the countable cofinality of $\Bbb R$ interleave a countable cofinal set into $\omega_1$. – Asaf Karagila Dec 06 '14 at 11:42
  • 1
    That makes sense, but I still don't get your opening sentence. 'First of all, the technical term is "cofinality of the cone generated by p", not "cramming ordinal of p".' The cofinality of the cone generated by $0$ in $\mathbb{R}$ is $\aleph_0,$ is it not? – goblin GONE Dec 07 '14 at 00:15
  • @goblin: I barely remember why I wrote something last week, so you expect me to remember something from two years ago? Don't be unreasonable. :-) – Asaf Karagila Dec 07 '14 at 05:07
  • :) So is the first sentence actually correct through? I don't get how the "cramming ordinal of $p$" is the same as "the cofinality of ${q\in P:q≥p}$" – goblin GONE Dec 07 '14 at 08:51
  • @goblin: It's probably a mistake, and includes an assumption that $P$ is somewhat homogeneous, so you can assume that every embedding is an unbounded embedding, which is the case in $\Bbb R$. Do remind me tomorrow, I'll give it some thought in the meantime. – Asaf Karagila Dec 07 '14 at 10:25
6

Here's a more elementary argument that any countable ordinal can be embedded into $\mathbb Q$. The trick is to show something stronger: any countable total order can embedded into $\mathbb Q$:

Let $(\mathbb N,{\sqsubset})$ be an arbitrary countable total order. (We can assume wlog that the underlying set is $\mathbb N$ -- that's what it means to be countable!) We defined an order monomorphism $f: (\mathbb N,{\sqsubset})\to(\mathbb Q,{<})$ by ordinary long induction on $\mathbb N$:

  • Arbitrarily set $f(0)=42$.

  • For $n>0$ suppose we have already decided what $f(m)$ is for $m<n$.

    If $n\sqsubset m$ for all $m<n$, then let $f(m)=\min_{m<n}f(m)-1$.

    If $m\sqsubset n$ for all $m<n$, then let $f(m)=\max_{m<n}f(m)+1$.

    Otherwise let $f(m)=\dfrac{\max_{m<n, m\,\sqsubset\, n}f(m) + \min_{m<n, n\,\sqsubset\, m}f(m)}{2}$

In fact essentially this construction shows that any countable total order can be embedded into any dense subset of $\mathbb R$.

Once we've mapped something into $\mathbb R$, we can remap it into $\mathbb R_+$, by composing with, say, $x\mapsto e^x$.

  • Thanks. Does that argument allow any countable total order to be embedded into any dense total order? – goblin GONE Apr 04 '13 at 09:18
  • 1
    @user18921: Yes. (If the dense total order has a maximum or minimum, start by picking two points in it and restrict your attention to the open interval between them). In this general case the argument requires the Axiom of Choice (or Dependent Choice). – hmakholm left over Monica Apr 04 '13 at 11:44