This started out as a question about Dedekind cuts and determining which of two interpretations of the definition of "Dedekind cut" is correct. While writing that question, I realized that I had unwittingly assumed that every real number is the limit of a convergent sequence of rationals.
This is a problem because 1) the set of such sequences may be countable depending on the definition of "convergence" and 2) "limits" define equivalence classes of such sequences, and the set of said equivalence classes may be countable even if the set of convergent sequences is not.
To lay down some ground rules, I know the set of all sequences of rational numbers ($\Bbb{Q}^\Bbb{N}$)to be uncountable, with cardinality equal to that of the power set of the integers ($2^{\aleph_0}$).$^{1}$
Now, the subset $S_Q$ of convergent sequences of rationals is a proper subset of $\Bbb{Q}^\Bbb{N}$ under all but one definition of "convergence" (that being "a sequence in $\Bbb{Q}$ converges iff it exists") so the possibility that the cardinality of the set of convergent sequences is strictly less than that of $\Bbb{Q}^\Bbb{N}$ - and potentially countable - is open.
If we restrict ourselves to either the set of definable or provably convergent sequences, then $S_Q$ is necessarily countable (proof sketch upon request). With that in mind, it seems reasonable that the set of convergent sequences of rationals must contain uncountably many undefinable members in order that the reals should remain uncountable.
Edit: I would add that "definable" here assumes a first-order theory in a countable language. I don't know anywhere near enough about pointclasses or hierarchies to discuss them in detail. For those interested, there are pointwise-definable models of ZFC in which every sequence of rationals is definable.
That being said, this doesn't help me unless I can figure out a way to prove the existence of convergent but not provably convergent sequences of rationals (even then, I would prefer to have a "witness").
Edit: the existence of convergent but not provably convergent sequences is equivalent to the existence of Cauchy but not provably Cauchy sequences of rationals that converge in $\Bbb{R}$. The existence of such sequences is implied by the uncountability of the set of Cauchy sequences which converge to $x$ for every real number $x$ (though no such sequence can be [directly] defined). This can be proven in ZF by modifying the diagonal argument as long as $\forall p\in\Bbb{Q}.\forall 0<\varepsilon.\exists q\in\Bbb{Q}.0<|p-q|<\varepsilon$ (which ought to follow from any proof that the rationals, under their usual ordering, are a dense subset of the reals).
Setting this aside and assuming that the set of all convergent sequences of rationals is uncountable, and that each real number is the limit of at least one such sequence, I encounter another problem. The sequence of rationals defining a particular real number is not unique - that is, two or more distinct sequences may have the same limit and thus represent the same real number (the proof is trivial).
If $R$ is an equivalence relation on $S_Q$ where $\displaystyle\forall\mathbf{a},\mathbf{b}\in S_Q.\mathbf{a}R\mathbf{b}\iff\lim_{n\to\infty}a_n=\lim_{n\to\infty}b_n$ then presumably $\Bbb{R}\cong S_Q/R$. For each $x\in\Bbb{R}$ the set of sequences in $\Bbb{Q}$ converging to $x$ is - admitting the aforementioned unprovably convergent sequences - uncountable. Because $S_Q=\bigcup (S_Q/R)$, $S_Q$ remains uncountable even if $S_Q/R$ is countable (since the countable union of uncountable sets is uncountable).
I'm not sure how to go about proving that $S_Q/R$ is uncountable, especially given that assuming $S_Q/R$ is countable without first assuming that $\Bbb{R}$ is uncountable fails to produce a contradiction.$^2$
Next Step
It at least seems plausible that $S_Q/R$ might be countable, but that my original premise (that every real is the limit of at least one convergent sequence of rationals) is false. If nothing else, we might consider that $S_Q/R$ represents something between the set of definable real numbers and the set of real numbers.
I would like to think that this is the case and that the number line can be filled in by adding nonconvergent sequences to $S_Q$. Intuitively, it would seem that the limit of a nonconvergent sequence cannot be a real number. However, since most real numbers are undefinable, and most such limits are undefined, it is in some ways more intuitive to think that equivalence classes of such nonconvergent sequences account for the remaining [undefinable] real numbers. Since the set of nonconvergent sequences has uncountably many uncountable subsets, the equivalence classes of nonconvergent sequences could account for the uncountability of the real numbers if $S_Q$ were countable.
While the construction of such equivalence classes is completely impossible in any sort of recursively definable sense, it might be possible to get a glimpse by assigning stages in the construction to a net over some uncountable space (think of something like an analogue Turing machine).
Footnotes:
$^1$I'm leaving continuum hypothesis and choice out of this question because that dead horse has been beaten enough and I'm not trying to start a war.
$^2$The easy way out would of course be to say that because $\Bbb{R}$ is uncountable, $S_Q/R$ must be uncountable. However, the purpose of this endeavor was to show that the real numbers, constructed using Dedekind cuts, are uncountable - at least, given a particular understanding of "Dedekind cut". Asserting that $S_Q/R$ is uncountable because the real numbers are and using this to show that the set of Dedekind cuts is uncountable ultimately amounts to saying "the reals are uncountable because the reals are uncountable" - which, while not strictly false, is not particularly insightful.