6

Let $n \in \mathbb{N}$. Using the Euclidean algorithm, it is straightforward to see that every natural number can be written as

$$n = \sum_{j=0}^m \epsilon_j(n) 2^j $$

where $\epsilon_j(n) \in \{0,1\}$.

Is there an easy way to show that this way of writing the number is unique?

  • 8
    Have you tried induction? – saulspatz Nov 28 '18 at 16:12
  • 8
    @stanleydodds Why are you answering in a comment? – Arthur Nov 28 '18 at 16:17
  • 4
    @stanleydodds Outlines of answers are still answers. Even one-line hints belong in answer posts in my opinion – Arthur Nov 28 '18 at 16:19
  • Index $j$ should start at $0$. If it starts at $1$ then RHS is even. – drhab Nov 28 '18 at 16:30
  • 3
    As presented, such expansions are not unique. For uniqueness, you need to add the constraint that $$\epsilon_m(n) = 1$$. Otherwise, an arbitrary number of additional leading 0 terms can be included to produce distinct expansions of the same n. – John Bollinger Nov 28 '18 at 17:54
  • You are correct, but I thought this was evident. –  Nov 28 '18 at 18:07
  • Well, it is evident that such a constraint is required for the uniqueness you assert, but it is not evident that we should accept the truth of that proposition in the first place. Multiple representations of the same number in the same base occur and must be accounted for in real-world situations, so the issue isn't even an obscure one. – John Bollinger Nov 29 '18 at 03:57

6 Answers6

8

How do you know the ordinary base $10$ expansion is unique?

Suppose digit strings $s$ and $t$ both represent the positive integer $n$. Then the units digit of each must be $d = n \pmod {10}$. So you can lop off both units digits. The lopped strings then both represent $(n-d)/10$.

Continue with the other digits (from the right) until you're done. Or, for a formal induction proof, apply that argument to the least $n$ with two representations to deduce a contradiction.

This argument works for any base. It's the standard algorithm for base conversion, finding the digits from right to left. It depends on knowing that you can do division with remainder, but not on the full strength of the Euclidean algorithm.

Ethan Bolker
  • 95,224
  • 7
  • 108
  • 199
7

Suppose $\exists n\in\Bbb N$ such that $n=\sum_{i\in A}2^i=\sum_{i\in B}2^i$ with $A,B\subset\Bbb N_0$. Then $\sum_{i\in A}2^i-\sum_{i\in B}2^i=0$ and so for set $C=A\Delta B$ (symmetric difference) and some function $s:C\rightarrow\{-1,1\}$ we have $\sum_{i\in C}s(i)2^i=0$. Now if $C\ne\emptyset$ then $C$ has a largest element (say $x$) and we have $\sum_{i\in C\backslash\{x\}}s(i)2^i=-s(x)2^x$ so $\sum_{i\in C\backslash\{x\}}-{s(i)\over s(x)}2^i=2^x$ but we now know $C\backslash\{x\}\subset\{0,1,2,...,x-1\}$ and also $-{s(i)\over s(x)}\le1$ so we have $\sum_{i\in C\backslash\{x\}}-{s(i)\over s(x)}2^i\le\sum_{i=0}^{x-1}2^i=2^{x}-1$ which is a contradiction. Hence $C=\emptyset$, so $A=B$, so the representations are in fact the same, hence the representation of n is unique (assuming it exists, which I gather has been shown already).

4

A very simple proof is by the pigeonhole principle. The key observation is that not only does any natural number $n$ have a binary expansion $$n = \sum_{j=0}^m \epsilon_j(n) 2^j,$$ but if $0\leq n<2^N$ then we need no powers of $2$ above $2^{N-1}$ so we can take $m=N-1$. Now, for any fixed $N$, there are $2^N$ natural numbers $n$ such that $0\leq n<2^N$ and $2^N$ different ways of choosing $\epsilon_j(n)\in\{0,1\}$ for each $j$ from $0$ to $N-1$. So, all $2^N$ of these binary expansions must have distinct sums, or else they would not be able to represent all $2^N$ of the different values of $n$.

This proves that for any $N$, a natural number $n$ has at most one binary expansion using powers of $2$ up to $2^{N-1}$. It follows that $n$ has only one binary expansion, up to adding $0$s at the start (since given two expansions of different lengths, you can always extend one by $0$s to make them the same length, and then they must become the same).

Eric Wofsey
  • 330,363
2

Not really an answer. But here's just a different way of framing your question which I think is neat.

Let $f: P_{fin}(\mathbb{N}) \to \mathbb{N}$ by $f(S) =\sum_{s\in S} 2^s$.

$f$ is onto. You have claimed this can be handled Euclidean algorithm.

What about $1-1$? We use the argument Stanley Dodds presented.

So we've seen that the set of all finite subsets of the natural numbers is in 1-1 correspondence with the set of natural numbers.

Mason
  • 3,792
2

It deserves to be better known that uniqueness of radix rep is a special case of the Rational Root Test, i.e. an integer root of an integer coef polynomial divides the least degree coef, e.g.

$\qquad11001_2 = g(2),\,\ \ g(x) = x^4+x^3+1$

$\qquad 10011_2 = h(2),\ \ h(x) = x^4+x+1$

If they're equal $\, 0 = g(2)-h(2) =: f(2)\,$ for $\,f = g-h = x(x^2-1)\,$ so $\,2\,$ is a root of $\,x^2-1\,$ so $\, 2^2 = 1\,\Rightarrow\, 2\mid 1,\,$ contradiction. This idea works generally - the nonzero coef's of $g-h$ are $\pm1$ contra the root $2$ must divide the least degree such coef. Below is the proof for general radix.


If $\,g(x) = \sum g_i x^i$ is a polynomial with integer coefficients $\,g_i\,$ such that $\,0\le g_i < b\,$ and $\,g(b) = n\,$ then we call $\,(g,b)\,$ a radix $\,b\,$ representation of $\,n.\,$ It is unique: $ $ if $\,n\,$ has another rep $\,(h,b),\,$ with $\,g(x) \ne h(x),\,$ then $\,f(x)= g(x)-h(x)\ne 0\,$ has root $\,b\,$ but all coefficients $\,\color{#c00}{|f_i| < b},\,$ contra the below slight generalization of: $ $ integer roots of integer polynomials divide their constant term.

Theorem $\ $ If $\,f(x) = x^k(\color{#0a0}{f_0}\!+f_1 x +\cdots + f_n x^n)=x^k\bar f(x)\,$ is a polynomial with integer coefficients $\,f_i\,$ and with $\,\color{#0a0}{f_0\ne 0}\,$ then an integer root $\,b\ne 0\,$ satisfies $\,b\mid f_0,\,$ so $\,\color{#c00}{|b| \le |f_0|}$

Proof $\ \ 0 = f(b) = b^k \bar f(b)\,\overset{\large b\,\ne\, 0}\Rightarrow\, 0 = \bar f(b),\,$ so, subtracting $\,f_0$ from both sides yields $$-f_0 =\, b\,(f_1\!+f_2 b+\,\cdots+f_n b^{n-1})\, \Rightarrow\,b\mid f_0\, \overset{\large \color{#0a0}{f_0\,\ne\, 0}}\Rightarrow\, |b| \le |f_0|\qquad {\bf QED}\qquad\quad$$

Bill Dubuque
  • 272,048
0

This argument is very basic but I think the notation is easy to follow: Suppose a number has two different expansions $\{a_i\}$ and $\{b_i\}$. Then $$ \sum_{i=0}^m a_i(n) 2^i = \sum_{i=0}^m b_i(n) 2^i $$ Break off the first term in both sums and you can get $$ a_o(n) - b_0(n) = 2\sum_{i=1}^m (b_i(n)-a_i(n)) 2^{i-1}$$ The l.h.s can only be ($0-0$), ($0-1$), ($1-0$), or ($1-1$), and it must be divisible by $2$, so it must equal $0$, i.e. $a_0(n) = b_0(n)$. Then you can divide by the $2$ in front of the sum, and repeat the argument (or use induction) to get $a_i(n) = b_i(n)$ for all $i$.

JonathanZ
  • 10,615