For this exposition we are launching off the theory of magnitudes platform and are assuming that we know nothing about $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},1,+)$ except that it satisfies $\text{P-0}$ thru $\text{P-5}$ and the theorem found here.
In this study of foundational logic, we've made a beeline drive to the automorphism group of $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},+)$ and assume we only have the following three theoretical concepts under our belts:
- The natural numbers (an inductive set),
$\quad (\mathbb N,(+,0),(1,*)) = \{0,1,2,\dots,n,\dots\}$
Note that we've only named the first $3$ numbers. We haven't 'discovered' Euclidean division or have a way of representing integers with a selected base.
-The integers,
$\quad (\mathbb Z,(+,0),(1,*)) =\{\dots,-n,\dots-2,-1,0,1,2,\dots,n,\dots\}$
-The theory of finite sets
We know that $(\mathbb N^{\gt 0},+)$ can be regarded as morphically contained in $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},+)$, but we've applied a 'forgetful functor' to the real numbers, and from here we can't even talk about the the rational numbers - there is no multiplication!.
Let us analyze the dilation automorphism, morphism $1 \mapsto 2$ on $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},+)$. We represent it with a name, $\mu_2$. It is easy to show that
$\tag 1 \sum_{k \in F} \mu_2^{k} \text{ with } F \text{ a finite subset of } \mathbb Z$
is an automorphism.
Of course when we apply it to the number $1$, numbers in $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},+)$ 'light up' (they get defined).
$\tag 2 \sum_{k \in F} \mu_2^{k} (1) = \sum_{k \in F} 2^{k}$
Let $\mathcal F (\mathbb Z)$ be the set of all finite subsets of $\mathbb Z$.
The following can be proven from this rudimentary logic platform:
Theorem 1: The mapping $F \mapsto \sum_{k \in F} \mu_2^{k}$ is an injection into the automorphism group.
The automorphisms are determined by where they send $1$, so we can also state
Theorem 2: If $\sum_{k \in F} 2^{k} = \sum_{k \in G} 2^{k}$ then the two finite sets $F$ and $G$ are identical.
So we can represent many numbers in $(\mathbb R^{\gt0},+)$. With a little effort we can show that $\sum_{k \in F} 2^{k}$ can only represent a positive integer when $F$ contains no negative integers.
The integer $1$ get represented since it corresponds to the identify automorphism applied to $1$, $\mu_2^{0}(1)$.
Assume $n$ can be represented. Using the identity
$\tag 3 2^k + 2^k = 2^{k+1}$
together with algebraic logic, we know that $n + 1$ is also represented.
Theorem 3: Every positive integer has a unique representation
$\tag 4 \sum_{k \in F} 2^{k}$
where $F$ has no negative integers.
So, without the notion of multiplication we have a representation theorem for integers.