32

Why is the topological definition of continuous in terms of open sets?

I think my main complaint might be that the notion of open set seems too flexible/general and considers too many things that don't seem the right notion of "closeness". Conceptually, people explain "continuous" as:

Nearby points map to nearby points.

But we can easily construct sets for which *all their points are not “nearby” but they are still open. A simple example in metric spaces: the union of two open balls. The sets are still open but the points in one ball vs the other are not nearby. However the topological definition is in terms of open sets so it would consider maps balls like this from $X$ to $Y$ while that doesn't seem right to me. Is there something that I am missing?

I guess I find it better to have a notion that captures the idea of “balls of radius epsilon in Y” to “balls of radius delta in X” a better notion of continuous.

Another issue I find with this is that I find this in conflict even with the traditional epsilon-delta definition. The way I see it is that the topological definition should be more general (and abstract) and should encompass the metric space definition as a special case. Which to me it’s not clear it does because there is this union of disjoint open sets issue, that seem get included in the topological definition but for me they shouldn’t. This point seems important. Why were open sets chosen as the correct notion? A better definition for me would be (instead of open sets) to be in terms of “balls of radius epsilon in Y” to “balls of radius delta in X” in some topological way to define this.

I have of course read the descriptions of open sets in wikiepdia but that doesn't seem to really clarify things. I know that open sets are the set of points under some topology that are "close". i.e. we only need sets to classify what points are considered "close". Which seems to me the main motivation why open sets were chosen, but the fact that disjoint open balls pass the test and are considered "close by" particularly disturbs me for some reason. Why is this specific complaint OK to ignore? What justifies not being worried about it?

Another reason I find it weird to use open sets is because for me open sets (since I am most familiar with the definition of open sets in metric spaces), are a type of set where everything is an interior point. It's a type of set that:

for all points we can always find a perturbation such that the point remains in the set (thus there is a neighbourhood that contains it in E).

I find this problematic since it doesn't seem the right notion of "nearby" (at least to me); the reasons I prefer the definition to be restricted to only single open balls or sets that have no weird gaps (continuous sets? for some definition of that). This interior point issue doesn't seem to be what continuity (or limits actually) encompass conceptually. Continuity/limits seem to be a property about getting closer and closer (at least conceptually) or approaching. Therefore, for me it would be better to define it in terms of sets that reflected this idea of closeness. Something like neighbourhoods or (open) balls like in the traditional way of defining balls $B_{\delta}(p) = { x \in X | d(x,p) < \delta}$. Since this seems to be a clear notion of "nearby". Why are these ideas not preferred? What is wrong with it?

amWhy
  • 209,954
  • 1
    https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/31859/what-concept-does-an-open-set-axiomatise/31946#31946. Not exactly an answer to your question but you may find it interesting. – Aurel Jul 10 '18 at 17:31
  • 1
    But there are equivalent ways of characterizing continuity. I mean, you can characterize continuity with closures too, which is fairly more intuitive in my opinion. Check here https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Continuity_Defined_by_Closure – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 17:32
  • 1
    @stressedout I think my way of thinking about closeness is not equivalent wrt to limits/continuity. I know I have not done the work to prove it formally, but it seems clearly stricter than open sets since I am upset about the union property of open sets applying too freely. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 17:34
  • What is your definition of a 'ball' in a space without a metric? – Steven Stadnicki Jul 10 '18 at 17:35
  • I'm still reading and thinking about your way, but meanwhile, you can check the link I sent about continuity with closures. Surely, the closure of a set is the set of all points arbitrarily close to it and then the definition of continuity with respect to closures becomes very intuitive and straightforward. It becomes "points close to a set are mapped to points close to its image". You can also think about the other definition $f(\lim_{n\to\infty}{a_n}) = \lim_{n\to\infty} f(a_n)$ which is more intuitive. – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 17:36
  • @StevenStadnicki I know thats part of the problem. I'm still working it out. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 17:36
  • 1
    I'm with @stressedout's comment that there are closure-defined versions of continuity, all equivalent to the "usual" open set versions, so who cares? Take your pick of what works best for you. I prefer the open set version because to say $|x-a| < \delta$ is the same as saying $x$ belongs to the open set $(a-\delta, a+\delta)$. That is how open sets capture "nearby." – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 17:37
  • But open sets are exactly the generalization of balls to non-metric spaces. – MPW Jul 10 '18 at 17:38
  • 3
    One can also define a topology (and also continuity) using "neighborhoods": https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Neighbourhood_(mathematics) – paf Jul 10 '18 at 17:38
  • @Randall I'm still digesting this closure thing. I'm not familiar with it. If you want to explain conceptually what its trying to say or how it similar or different (at least conceptually) it would make it easier. Meanwhile back to reading the proof and what it exactly means. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 17:40
  • @Pinocchio Then I would invest some time learning about closures and limit points and the equivalence of all the different versions of continuity. Consult any decent point-set book. It's not too hard to follow and kind of enlightening. – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 17:42
  • @Randall I do know what those things are since I'm familiar with at least real analysis and metric spaces...I'm just not seeing the connection (closure property has) with my question and open sets complaint...just yet. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 17:43
  • 5
    I think the source of your complaint is that open sets can contain points very far away (therefore not "close"). That's true. But continuity does not demand that the inverse image of one open set be open, but for ALL of them to be open, no matter how small. – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 17:44
  • @Randall oh! That might be it. Duh. I will let this sink and see if it really was all the sources of my complaint. Feel free to add an answer, I think it would really help me (and hopefully others too). – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 17:47
  • @Pinocchio I'll let someone else try it. I'm supposed to be working now. – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 17:47
  • You could also understand a topology as a notion of "for $p$ close enough to $x_0$, $\phi(p)$": define this to be notation for "${ x \in X \mid \phi(x) }$ is a neighborhood of $x_0$". So then $f:X\to Y$ being continuous at $x_0$ can be interpreted as: for any predicate $\phi$ on $Y$, if $\phi(y)$ for $y$ close enough to $f(x_0)$, then $\phi(f(x))$ for $x$ close enough to $x_0$. – Daniel Schepler Jul 10 '18 at 19:24
  • This answer may be of interest to you. –  Jul 11 '18 at 03:57
  • "we can easily construct sets which all its points are not “nearby” but its still open." So what? It's not continuous if one weirdly big open set maps to open. It's true if all open sets map to open sets. So who cares if we can make huge open sets. It's that all open sets no matter how small map to open sets that is important. – fleablood Jul 11 '18 at 15:31
  • 1
    ""we can easily construct sets which all its points are not “nearby” but its still open." I'm not sure you can make an open set in which all points are not "nearby" to any other points. – fleablood Jul 11 '18 at 15:35
  • @fleablood thats sounds really weird, if open is not suppose to capture the concept of closeness then what is it capturing? – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 17:27
  • @user170039 not sure if I was able to really appreciate Scottie's answer. He's brilliant but I'm not sure I really got it... – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 17:35
  • @Pinocchio So.... if you are agreeing with me, why are saying it seems weird? – fleablood Jul 18 '18 at 18:15
  • @fleablood where did I agree with you? – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 19:18
  • @Pinocchio You: "if open is not suppose to capture the concept of closeness then what is it capturing?" Me: " I'm not sure you can make an open set in which all points are not "nearby" to any other points." Those two statements convey the exact same concept. – fleablood Jul 18 '18 at 19:25
  • @fleablood I'm sorry if I'm to dense (or to inexperienced in this area) but I asked a question, so it's not clear to me I am suggesting a concept. I am confused on what open sets are suppose to be. I guess they aren't suppose to mean nearby sets but more that every point in the open set when perturbed is within the open set (the way I learned it...or that there is always a set containing the point within the greater open set in question). I think thats what I was asking, that doesn't seem to me to be the concept of "closeness". – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 19:28
  • 1
    Open is about "closeness". An open set is one in which for every point in the set. You can get "close enough" to the point so that there is an open neighborhood entirely in the set. It doesn't mater how big the whole set is, so long as for every point there is a small neighborhood around the point completely in the set. So take the interior of a unit circle at the origin and union it with a giant blob without an edge a million miles away. That is still open. Every point in the circle has a tiny neighborhood around it and every point in the blob has a tiny point around it. – fleablood Jul 18 '18 at 19:47
  • 1
    It doesn't matter if the points of the circle are a million miles away from the blog. There are other points that are nearby to make the open neighborhood. – fleablood Jul 18 '18 at 19:48
  • @fleablood maybe my confusion stems that for an open set the set is "fixed". But when defining a open set we only require that there exists a nbhd that contains the point. I guess I never realized that by the existence of any nbhd any nbhd smaller works (no matter how small one makes it). But your point seems to be different, it means that you can always get close enough to every point with points within the open set, in that sense its "close". Is that correct? – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 20:16

9 Answers9

29

I think what User Randall wrote in a comment is the main point: Only half of the emphasis in the definition of continuity as

The inverse images of all open sets are open

should lie on

The inverse images of all open sets are open

but at least half of it on

The inverse images of all open sets are open.

The intuition is that a set is open if around each point inside, there is still some wiggle room a.k.a. neighburhood around it. Granted that some open sets in a metric space also contain some points "far away", as in your example with the disjoint union of two balls -- but now that is where the all in the definition kicks in: To check continuity, you will also have to consider single balls. Really, really small single balls. All of them.

And in a metric space, it is clear that checking it for "very small" balls, small as in "your favourite $\epsilon$", suffices to prove it for all. Without a metric, it's harder to tell which open sets are small, so, well, let's just make the definition robust and demand it for all of them. (Actually, sometimes it suffices to check on various kinds of "basic" open sets.)

So the "all" is a placeholder for arbitrarily small, which technically does not make sense in a general topological space. As soon as it does -- in a metric space --, you can replace "all" by "arbitrarily small", and making that rigorous will give the usual $\epsilon-\delta$-definition back.

  • 1
    +1 for getting to the heart of the issue. – Paramanand Singh Jul 13 '18 at 01:07
  • 1
    thanks for pointing out that "arbitrarily small" doesn't really make sense in topology. I think that a subtle detail I could have missed and find valuable. The all is really a placeholder for it, thanks! – Charlie Parker Jul 18 '18 at 17:21
  • @Pinocchio: Maybe you also want to have a look at this question and its answers I just came across. It focuses more on a "pointwise" view which is closer to the one one is used to from real calculus / metric spaces -- but still, one demands something about "all" neighbourhoods as opposed to the "arbitrarily small" $\epsilon$-balls which one has as soon as there's a metric: https://math.stackexchange.com/q/96324/96384 – Torsten Schoeneberg Jul 21 '18 at 04:11
20

I personally have always had problem with the definition of continuity with respect to open sets. And my issue is not that open sets are too general, but my issue is that the definition looks sort of twisted and counter-intuitive to what one would expect it to be.

If $f: X\to Y$ is a mapping between two topological spaces $X$ and $Y$, then $f$ is continuous if and only if $f^{-1}(U)$ is an open subset of $X$ for any $U$ that is open is $Y$. In metric spaces, we know that a set is open if we can find a ball of small enough radius centered around each of its points. So, one can easily see that this definition does imply the good old $\epsilon-\delta$ definition of continuity that we were taught in calculus.

But still, the idea of working with inverse images looks mysterious to me. A more natural looking definition, which is equivalent, is the definition that uses the idea of closures in topology. $f$ is continuous if and only if

$$f(\mathrm{cl}(S)) \subseteq\mathrm{cl}(f(S))$$

is true for any set $S \subseteq X$. First of all, it looks more natural because we're working with $f$ and not $f^{-1}$. Secondly, a closure of a set $S$ is the set of all points that are arbitrarily "close" to it and therefore, this statement says that $f$ is continuous if and only if it sends close points to an arbitrary set $S$, to points that are close to its image.

If you are in a good topological space like a metric space, you can define the closure of a set using the idea of the limit of a sequence. A point is in the closure if there exists a sequence that approaches toward it. Then $f$ can be equivalently defined as being continuous if and only if

$$\lim_{n\to\infty}f(a_n)=f(\lim_{n\to\infty}a_n)$$

This is also more familiar and in essence is very similar to saying that $f$ maps nearby points to nearby points.

Now, there are at least four axiomatic ways to define abstract topology: using the properties of open sets, using the properties of closed sets, using the properties of neighborhoods and using the properties of the closure operator which is due to Kuratowski if I'm not mistaken. It can be very instructive to check that all of these axiomatic systems turn out to be equivalent and see how continuity is defined in each of them.

Metric spaces in analysis are a special case of the first system of axioms for topology (open sets) where our space has a basis of open balls, because the definition of an open ball is very straightforward when we have a metric on $X$.

stressed out
  • 8,130
  • 15
    I am all for people finding their own soul-mate version of continuity. I would argue, however, that the open set version is IMHO far superior for arguments on compactness, connectedness, Hausdorffness, etc. (Since top'l concepts are defined on open sets and not something else.) – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 17:56
  • @Randall I may agree or disagree. I personally have never felt comfortable with the open cover definition of compactness for example. I find it easier to think about sequences when I want to prove something about compactness in metric spaces. The only issue is that filters and nets are a tad complicated in general topological spaces. :( – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 18:01
  • 2
    Well, I would also contradict myself slightly and argue for flexibility in whatever you do. For some analytically-inclined fields, other versions may be better suited, all depending. It's a matter of taste and genetics – Randall Jul 10 '18 at 18:03
  • 1
    Really helpful answer. I think I will need more time to really digest it, especially your new perspective using closure. One comment, why do you find it weird to work with inverse mappings? – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 19:13
  • I also found it weird at first until I was taught that by doing this one is actually starting with the "for all epsilon" part of the usual definition, then since we require it to be open (nearby points) and the inverse image to also be (nearby points) it results in the definition of continuity. I learned this when I asked this question: https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/2823758/why-is-the-topological-definition-of-continuous-the-way-it-is?noredirect=1&lq=1

    I'd be interested to know what you think about this since you seem to have a good understanding of this subject (better than me).

    – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 19:14
  • 1
    @Pinocchio Yes, you're right that it works because it's a generalization of the $\epsilon-\delta$ definition, but it's still sort of counter-intuitive to me. It's a psychological thing of course, not a mathematical thing. The inverse image of a set can generally look weird. For example, the inverse image of a ball under a continuous function can be an infinite number of complicated looking open sets. While the image of a compact set under a continuous function is compact, or the image of a connected set under a continuous function is connected. But it's just psychological as I said. – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 19:31
  • @stressedout I'm curious, is your psychological concern that the definition of continuity (wether topological or $\epsilon-\delta$) because the definition starts with all $\epsilon$'s? Or is it more focused because start with inverse images? With the mathematical tools I have, it seems unavoidable to start with epsilon because we always start by specifying an epsilon first so we specify an open set $U$ in the target space $Y$ first and then we look for a delta, which is essentially the inverse map, then we require it to be open cuz open means close. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 19:45
  • I'm really curious to understand your psychological complaint because for I think I strongly empathize with your complaint. This may not apply to you completely but I'm still don't understand 100% to my satisfaction why we start with $\epsilon$ first. I understand it a bit better but I wouldn't say I know why we specify the open set in $Y$ first or why open maps are not just the natural definition of continuous (since hey, open maps is mapping close things to close thing, so why isn't that the definition of continuous). – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 19:47
  • If you mention limits of sequences in this general context, perhaps you could point out that if sequences are generalized to nets then limits can be used to characterize continuity in arbitrary spaces. – John Coleman Jul 10 '18 at 19:48
  • @JohnColeman You're right. I decided to avoid the concepts of nets and filters for two reasons: 1. My answer had already become too long and too long is tiring and boring, 2. I think the OP already has a lot to digest and (s)he can learn about nets and filters at a later time. – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 19:49
  • @Pinocchio we start with $\epsilon$ first because we want to say "no matter how close we want to get to $f(a)$, we can always do so by choosing a small enough neighborhood around $a$". The wording of this statement should tell you why we say "for all epsilon", "there exists a delta"... Do you see my point? I can explain more if it's still not clear. My psychological complaint is rather psychological, I don't know how to put it mathematically. xD There's no mathematical difference between these definitions in reality. – stressed out Jul 10 '18 at 19:52
12

It appears that most of your confusion comes from your notion of continuity being tightly coupled to the notion of a metric space. But in fact the notion of continuity for metric spaces is tremendously natural, and it is not necessary to define concepts like open balls or open sets to get at continuous functions over metric spaces.

However for functions between non-metric spaces, one cannot simply decide about what being "close" or "near" means, or even define what a "ball" is. It is in these cases that topologies and open sets shine.

One should note that there isn't anything special about open sets vs closed sets. It is perfectly reasonable to define topologies and continuity in terms of closed sets. (And in fact it is sometimes easier, such as in algebraic geometry).

Relatedly, you also seem to conflate the idea of two points being close and two points being contained in a single open set (in particular, you seem to dislike it when this open set is formed as a union of disjoint open balls in a metric space). But in fact any two points in any topological space are contained in an open set: namely the whole space (which is open). The intuition that being in an open set somehow means that two elements are close is a very dull intuition, and should be sharpened.

It is somehow better to think of two points as being close if they are contained in "lots" of open sets. And still this intuition leaves room for more careful examination.

6

I'm not sure why open balls are any better than open sets at capturing the notion of "closeness". If a ball has radius 1000000, the points in it won't be close in any sense. What you seem to be thinking of is not a particular open ball, but rather the set of all open balls around a point $p$. This more accurately captures the $\epsilon-\delta$ definition, as in that definition you are allowed to make $\delta$ as small as you like. Thus you may choose the open ball so that the points in it are arbitrarily near to $p$. Now, you can also do this for open sets, since every open ball is an open set.

This is formalized by the idea of a neighborhood basis, defined as any collection $N_p$ of open neighborhoods of $p$ which are ``arbitrarily small'' in the sense that if $U$ is any open set containing $p$, then there is a set in $N_p$ which is a subset of $U$. If the topological space is a metric space, we can take $N_p$ to be the set of all balls centered at $p$.

By making the neighborhoods become smaller and smaller, we can recover the idea of closeness encapsulated by the $\epsilon-\delta$ definition. To be precise, suppose $X$ and $Y$ are metric spaces, and let $p$ be a point of $X$. Choose an arbitrarily small element of the neighborhood basis of $f(p)$, that is, a ball $B_\epsilon(f(p))$ for arbitrarily small $\epsilon$. If $f$ is continuous in the topological sense, then $f^{-1}(B_\epsilon(f(p))$ is open, and it contains $p$, so it must contain some open ball $B_\delta(p)$. To say that $f(B_\delta(p))\subseteq B_\epsilon(f(p))$ means that if $|p_1-p|<\delta$, then $|f(p_1)-f(p)|<\epsilon$, which is the $\epsilon-\delta$ definition of continuity.

This shows that we can recover the $\epsilon-\delta$ definition by only applying the topological definition to those open subsets of $Y$ which happen to be open balls. Conversely, suppose we know that $f^{-1}(B_\epsilon(q))$ is open for all balls $B_\epsilon(q)$ in $Y$. Then it must follow that $f^{-1}(V)$ is open for every open set $V$. To see this, write $V=\bigcup_\alpha B_\alpha$ as a union of balls $B_\alpha$ (which we can do since $V$ is open). Then $f^{-1}(V)=\bigcup_\alpha f^{-1}(B_\alpha)$. By hypothesis, each $f^{-1}(B_\alpha)$ is open, therefore $f^{-1}(V)$ is also open.

Thus we could give an alternative characterization of continuity by simply requiring that $f^{-1}(V)$ be open when $V$ is an element of the neighborhood basis. However, if for $q\in Y$ we take $N_q$ to be the set of all open sets containing $q$, this is also a neighborhood basis, and so we see that this isn't so different from the usual definition.

I will remark that for a metric space, there is also a countable neighborhood basis of any point $p$, obtained by considering only those balls $B_\delta(p)$ where $\delta\in\mathbb Q^+$. This is essentially what allows us to express continuity in terms of limits, as in stressed out's answer.

Finally, let me address the issue of disjoint open sets. Suppose $V$ is an open neighborhood of $f(p)$ in $Y$ such that $f^{-1}(V)$ is a union of two disjoint open sets $U_1$ and $U_2$ in $X$, where, say, $p\in U_1$. If we consider $U_1$ to be the "nearby" points, all this says is that there are also some "non-nearby" points (in $U_2$) which map into $V$, which is not a problem.

6

You seem to have a misconception about what the notion of openness is supposed to represent. You write:

I know that open sets are the set of points under some topology that are close. i.e. we only need sets to classify what points are considered close. Which seems to me the main motivation why open sets were chosen, but the fact that disjoint open ball pass the test and are considered close by particularly disturbs me for some reason. Why is this specific complaint ok to ignore? What justifies not being worried about it?

It's not true that an open set is a set of points that are "close together". Open sets do not, and are not supposed to, be sets of points that are "all close to each other". That's why it's fine a union of disjoint open balls is considered an open set: contrary to what you write here, disjoint open balls are not "considered close by".

It looks like this is at the core of your confusion. Maybe things will make more sense now?

Tanner Swett
  • 10,624
  • 1
    but then how does using the open sets the right notion of continuity if we want to capture the idea of mapping "nearby points to nearby points"? How do we justify that idea if we use open sets? Is it because we consider all open sets? There has to be somewhere the notion of closeness/nearby for continuity to actually capture the concept we want it to capture. Right? I just don't see where the current definition does capture this. – Charlie Parker Jul 10 '18 at 22:30
  • I don't know how the definition of continuity captures the idea of mapping nearby points to nearby points, so I can't really answer that. This answer I posted a while back explains how I think of continuity myself: https://math.stackexchange.com/a/1795995/13524 – Tanner Swett Jul 11 '18 at 00:13
  • @Pinocchio Not sure if this will help, but I think the relation of "nearby" to open sets - loosely speaking - is that if you know that an open set contains a point, the same set must also contain other nearby points (given a situation where "nearby" makes sense). It's not that all other points in the set have to be nearby, only that some have to be nearby. – David Z Jul 11 '18 at 01:50
2

Not every topological space is metric so the notion of distance is out of question for general topological spaces thus we can not measure if two points are close to each other or not.

Open sets are there to generalize the concepts such as continuity to all topological spaces without applying the distance and $\epsilon-\delta$ terminology.

If the inverse image of open sets are open then the function is continuous, is much easier than " For every epsilon there exists a delta....."

  • "the notion of closeness is out of question " Isn't a closed sets simply defined as the complement of an open set? – Surb Jul 10 '18 at 19:48
  • "If the inverse image of open sets are open then the function is continuous, is much easier than " For every epsilon there exists a delta....."" Really? How do you usually verify that a set is open? – Surb Jul 10 '18 at 19:50
  • 1
    @Surb By closeness I meant two points being close to each other not a set being closed. Regarding your second comment, open sets are well defined in any topology. – Mohammad Riazi-Kermani Jul 10 '18 at 20:32
2

In analogy to metric spaces, let's use the (not-formally defined) term "ball around $x$" to mean the open set of points which are close to $x$ by some reasonable notion of closeness. The stricter your notion of closeness, the smaller the ball. If you want something more formal, you can take "balls" to be elements of a basis for the topology, if you've heard of that. The right intuitive notion of "$U$ is an open set" is not "$U$ is a ball" but rather "$U$ is a union of balls."

Now let's look at the definition of continuity. "$f$ is continuous at $x$ if for all open $U \ni f(x)$, we have $f^{-1}(U)$ open." The first thing to note is that if $f^{-1}(U)$ and $f^{-1}(V)$ are both open, then so is $f^{-1}(U \cup V) = f^{-1}(U) \cup f^{-1}(V)$. So the definition holds if it works for all balls, since an arbitrary open set is a union of balls. When you restrict your attention to balls, this is exactly the topological analogue of the epsilon-delta definition in metric spaces.

nkm
  • 2,466
  • 10
  • 17
2

The most intuitive definition of continuity is indeed

nearby points map to nearby points

On the other side open subsets can be crazily complicated, and as already noted in other responses, they may contain points arbitrarily "far". In fact any two different points in a Hausdorff topology are "far" in the sense that they have disjoint neighborhoods. Unless you have a metric, all points are equally "far" one another.

The key observation is that the most direct formalization of the above definition is using neighborhoods, so

The inverse image of any neighborhood of $f(x)$ includes a neighborhood of $x$

From neighborhoods to topology

Given the full map $\mathfrak{N}: S \to \wp(\wp(S))$ of neighborhoods of points of a set $S$, such that

  • $\forall x \in S, \forall N\in \mathfrak{N}[x] \quad x\in N$
  • $\forall x \in S, \forall N\in \mathfrak{N}[x], \forall B\in\wp(S) \quad N \subseteq B \implies B\in \mathfrak{N}[x]$
  • $\forall x \in S, \forall M\in \mathfrak{N}[x], \forall N\in \mathfrak{N}[x] \quad M\cap N \in \mathfrak{N}[x]$
  • $\forall x \in S, \forall N\in \mathfrak{N}[x] \quad \exists M \in\mathfrak{N}[x] : M \subseteq N \land \forall y \in M: N \in \mathfrak{N}[y]$

you can very well define a topology on a space $S$, by defining open sets as those that contain neghborhoods of all their points:

$T = \{A \in \wp(S) : \forall x \exists N (N \in \mathfrak{N}[x] \land (x\in A \implies x\in N \subseteq A)) \}$

With this definition, it turns out that inverse images of open sets by a continuous function are open.

From topology to neighborhoods

As one can see, a "neighborhoodogy" is quite a complicated beast, a function that maps from points to "parts of parts of the space", subject to quite complex rules. On the other hand, a topology is much simpler, it's just a single subset of "parts of the space" $T \subseteq \wp(S)$, again with some rules, but less so.

  • $\emptyset \in T$
  • $S \in T$
  • $\forall \mathcal{F}\subseteq T \quad \bigcup\mathcal{F}\in T$
  • $\forall P\in T, \forall Q\in T \quad P\cap Q\in T$

We can then define neighborhoods of a point with

$\mathfrak{N}[x] = \{N \in \wp(S) : \exists O(O\in T \land x\in O \subseteq N)\}$

and continuous functions as those for which inverse images of open sets are open.

It turns out that the same property for neighborhoods are preserved, so the two definitions are completely equivalent. And the one based on topology is much simpler, requiring less concepts, less rules and less steps.

This is why it's commonly used as the preferred definition.

rewritten
  • 3,092
0

I guess I find it better to have a notion that captures the idea of “balls of radius epsilon in Y” to “balls of radius delta in X” a better notion of continuous.

Your own Wikipedia link provides part of the answer:

In practice, however, open sets are usually chosen to provide a notion of nearness that is similar to that of metric spaces, without having a notion of distance defined. In particular, a topology allows defining properties such as continuity, connectedness, and compactness, which were originally defined by means of a distance.