This has been answered many many times on this site, but here is a simple reason. If one would use any other truth table for $P\to Q$ it would no longer mean what it is supposed to. If the hypothesis $P$ is true, then everyone agrees that $P\to Q$ should hold if and only if $Q$ does. Now suppose the hypothesis $P$ is false. If one would define (as you suggest) $P\to Q$ to be false in this case, regardless of $Q$, then $P\to Q$ would be true only if both $P$ and $Q$ are true, making it a symmetric operation for which we already have a name (namely "and", written $P\land Q$). If instead when $P$ is false we would define $P\to Q$ to be true only if $Q$ is, then the meaning of $P\to Q$ would ignore the status of the hypothesis $P$ completely, and be equivalent to $Q$. Finally if when $P$ is false we would define $P\to Q$ to be true only if $Q$ is false, then $P\to Q$ would be true if any only if $P$ and $Q$ have the same truth value, again a symmetric relation that does not reflect what we mean by implication. So the only reasonable option is the define, when the hypothesis is false, the relation $P\to Q$ to be true regardless of $Q$.
And this actually captures what one wants to say pretty well: if the hypothesis is true then we claim the conclusion must be true as well, but if the hypothesis is false, we did not mean to claim anything, so we shouldn't be called out for making a false claim in such cases.
Intuitively speaking, you may view the rule of inference this way. If your teacher promise you (weirdly) that "if you get an A+ this time, then you can graduate directly from then on under my permission", then when will he break the promise? When and only when you get an A+ that time and he does not make your graduation happen!
– Yes Aug 16 '17 at 12:24