9

This is problem 1.2.20 from Hatcher's algebraic topology.

enter image description here

I am able to complete the first part. But I have trouble proving they are homotopy equivalent but not homeomorphic. Can someone please give some hints? Thanks.

JSCB
  • 13,456
  • 15
  • 59
  • 123
  • Maybe you will find interesting https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/69698/wedge-sum-of-circles-and-hawaiian-earring – mfl Jul 10 '17 at 14:11
  • I just found out that my proof for part one is wrong... – JSCB Jul 10 '17 at 14:53
  • Let me call the wedge $Y$. To define $g:Y\to X$, fix a homeomorphism $h$ from $S^1$ to the line $x=1$ in the Riemann sphere. Send the $n$-th copy of $S^1$ in the wedge to the line $x=\frac{1}{2n}$ in the Riemann sphere, by using $h$ and then mapping the line $x=1$ to the line $x=\frac{1}{2n}$ by translation. Finally send all the lines $x=\frac{1}{2n}$ to X by doing inversion in the Riemann sphere with respect to the unit circle. To define $f:X\to Y$ send the point $nz+n$ with $n\in\mathbb{N}$ and $|z|=1$ to the point $z$ in the $n$-th copy of $S^1$ in the wedge. – Bettybel Jul 10 '17 at 18:24
  • The non-homeomorphism is has been answered before. – Bettybel Jul 10 '17 at 20:05
  • See here : http://web.math.ku.dk/~moller/blok1_05/AT-ex.pdf . But can someone explain why $\bar{X}$ is homotopy equivalent to $X$? – user302934 Oct 15 '20 at 12:55
  • For the non-homeomorphsim bit, assuming the wedge is countable, I think you could use the observation that that infinite wedge of circles can be thought of as a subset of a torus with inner radius zero. Arrange the circles so that for each $n\in \mathbb{N}$, there's a circle pointing in the $\frac{2\pi}{n}$ direction (sort of making a slinky shape with "most" of the circles getting pushed very close to the circle hovering at $2\pi$). This set will be compact, but the growing wedge of circles won't be. – gdd Oct 22 '20 at 01:34
  • 2
    @GaryD $\bar{X}=X\cup ({0}\times \Bbb R)$. The map $\bar{X}\to X$ that fixes $X$ and sending the $y$-axis to the origin is not continuous. – user302934 Oct 22 '20 at 07:16
  • @user302934 I understand. I gave it some more thought and supplied an answer on your post: https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/3875899/the-closure-of-the-union-of-growing-circles-in-bbb-r2/3877629#3877629 – gdd Oct 23 '20 at 05:30
  • @A.Chu I think I've found a better (and shorter) answer for the homotopic equivalence. – user326210 Oct 24 '20 at 03:16
  • 5
  • This should not be marked as duplicate. The linked question does not have an answer explaining why the two spaces are homotopy equivalent. – Alex G. Nov 08 '21 at 18:45

1 Answers1

14

Comparing the topology of the nested-circle space X and the wedge-sum space Y.

Not homeomorphic

Here's the visual intuition. The problem for homeomorphism is that the wedge sum makes all the circle-copies $S^1$ independent of one another. You can make an open set in $Y$ by choosing one arc (such as the red curve, above) independently from each of the circles; the union of arcs is an open set.

In contrast, the circles of $X$ are clustered together at the origin. Any open neighborhood of the origin will intersect all of the circles, and the resulting arc lengths (blue curves) are not independent of each other. Instead, we know that the neighborhood contains an open ball around the origin, and so each curve must be at least as long as the ball's radius.

This is the fundamental difference between the two topologies: In both $X$ and $Y$, the neighborhoods of the origin include families of arcs, one per circle. In $Y$, the arcs from different circles may have arbitrary lengths. In $X$, the arcs always have some lower limit $r$.

You can use this intuition to prove that $X$ is first countable (it's a subspace of a metric space $\mathbb{R}^2$) but $Y$ is not; hence they're not homeomorphic. ($Y$ is not first countable: for any collection $B_1, B_2, \ldots,$ of neighborhoods of the origin, you can find for each $B_k$ a "red arc" $A_k$ in the $k$th circle that is sufficiently small that it does not contain $B_k$; from the combination of these arcs, you can obtain a neighborhood $ \bigvee A_k$ of the origin that (by diagonal argument) contains none of the $B_k$; hence the collection $B_1,B_2,\ldots$ isn't a neighborhood basis. It can be useful to think about why this construction doesn't transfer over to $X$.)

...but homotopy equivalent

The intuition that $X$ and $Y$ are homotopy equivalent: note that you can construct either space following the same construction technique: start with an infinite disjoint union of circles $\coprod_\infty S^1$, select one point from each circle, and glue the selected points together. In other words, $X$ and $Y$ are cell complexes made of the same parts and constructed in the same way.

Here's one way to construct a homotopy equivalence explicitly. There's a bijective map $f:Y\rightarrow X$ that sends circles to circles in the obvious way, mapping the origin onto the origin. Roughly speaking, it is continuous because $Y$ includes all the same open sets as $X$ (plus some more).

Next, in the space $X$, consider a small closed ball around the origin, say of radius $r=1/4$. There is a continuous map $\alpha:X\rightarrow X$ which shrinks all points in the ball to the origin, pulling the rest of each circle closed. This map is continuous and moreover homotopic to the identity (you can gradually shrink the ball to a point.)

A bouquet of circles, with a circular region quotiented to a point.

There is a bijective function $\tilde{g}:X\rightarrow Y$ which sends circles to circles, mapping the origin onto the origin. It is not continuous, because there's no analogue in $X$ to the open neighborhoods made of arbitrary-sized arcs through the origin in $Y$. In contrast, the composition $g \equiv \tilde g\circ \alpha$ repairs this problem— it is continuous. Indeed, then the inverse image of every neighborhood of the origin in $Y$ contains the previously shrunk-to-zero ball of radius 1/4.

The pair $f$ and $g$ comprise the homotopic equivalence. The composition $f\circ g:X\rightarrow X$ is just the map $\alpha$ again, which shrinks the $1/4$-radius ball to zero. The composition $g\circ f:Y\rightarrow Y$ performs an analogue of that quotienting operation on $\bigvee_\infty S^1$, sending various arcs of the origin, one from each circle, to the base point. It is similarly homotopic to the identity.

user326210
  • 17,287
  • The map $\bar{X}\to X$, sending the $y$-axis to the origin, and fixing $X$ is not continuous, I think, because $\bar{X}$ is the closure of $X$. – user302934 Oct 22 '20 at 07:15
  • The set $Y$ is not open in $\bigvee_1^\infty S^1$, because in particular it is not open when intersected with each of its subspaces $S^1$. You would still need a neighbourhood in each copy of $S^1$. The difference between $X$ and $Y$ is that those neighbourhoods in $Y$ can become arbitrarily small. – abhi01nat Oct 22 '20 at 08:51
  • @abhi01nat Thank you; you're right. The preimage of the red arc under the quotient map from $\coprod_\infty S^1$ is not an open set. How to draw a better picture? – user326210 Oct 22 '20 at 09:01
  • I'm not sure; one way perhaps is to note that any neighbourhood of the basepoint in $X$ will contain a "minimum" ball, that is each circle has an open set of at least a given size. This is not true in $Y$ where the neighbourhoods can be of arbitrary sizes, so the picture can show smaller and smaller arcs shrinking to a point. – abhi01nat Oct 22 '20 at 09:33