3

I am trying to get an intuition (ohh, the irony) about the logical truth tables. In particular, I am looking at the basic conditional $P\implies Q$ with the following truth table:

$$\begin{array}{c|c|c} P & Q & P\implies Q \\ \hline \text{T} & \text{T} & \text{T} \\ \hline \text{F} & \text{T} & \text{T} \\ \hline \text{T} & \text{F} & \text{F} \\ \hline \text{F} & \text{F} & \text{T} \end{array}$$

How does one obtain this truth table? If it is an axiom, what is the motivation behind this particular form?

2 Answers2

4

There is a long-standing debate whether or not the conditional is truth-functional in the first place (that is: is the truth-value of $P \to Q$ a function of the truth-values of $P$ and $Q$?).

But if we treat it as such (that is: if we had to pick one of the truth-tables), then here is an argument for setting the truth-values as we do.

Consider Modus Ponens:

$$P \rightarrow Q$$

$$P$$

$$\therefore Q$$

Now suppose $P = T$ and $Q = F$. If $T \rightarrow F$ were set to $T$, then this argument would be invalid! Clearly that's not what we want. So, we should set $T \rightarrow F = F$

Now let's consider:

$$P \rightarrow P$$

OK, clearly we want this to be a tautology, no matter what $P$ is saying, and no matter whether $P$ is true or false ( Indeed, even if $P$ is a contradiction, it should still hold that ' If P then P'!). OK, but this means that we can't set $T \rightarrow T$ to $F$, for then $P \rightarrow P$ would not be a tautology, so we set $T \rightarrow T = T$. Likewise, we can't set $F \rightarrow F$ to $F$, so we set $F \rightarrow F = T$.

Finally, we want $\rightarrow$ to be 'asymmetrical' or non-commutative: clearly 'if P then Q' is completely different from 'if Q then P'. But given the other truth-values already set as they are, if we set $F \rightarrow T$ to $F$, then it would become commutative! So, we set $F \rightarrow T =T$.

In short, setting the truth-values as we do is the only way to ensure:

  1. Modus Ponens is valid

  2. $P \rightarrow P$ is a tautology

  3. $\to$ is non-commutative

And, just to have some more arguments for setting the truth-values as we do, consider:

$$P \rightarrow Q$$

$$Q$$

$$\therefore P$$

This should clearly be an invalid argument, with the counterexample of $P = F$ and $Q = T$. But if we were to set $F \rightarrow T$ to $F$, this would not be a counterexample at all! So, we better set $F \rightarrow T = T$.

Finally, let's note that we want:

$$P \rightarrow Q \Leftrightarrow \neg Q \rightarrow \neg P$$

This means that $T \rightarrow T$ and $F \rightarrow F$ better have the same truth-value. So, once you are convinced that one of them should be $T$, then this contraposition equivalence should convince you that the other should be $T$ as well.

amWhy
  • 209,954
Bram28
  • 100,612
  • 6
  • 70
  • 118
  • I reversed my downvote, but I think the links above, and any search on MSE using logic, material conditional, logical implication has long before beaten this topic to death. It's not wrong, but it's not entirely correct, either. – amWhy Sep 24 '17 at 19:10
2

First, you should know that it is better (and more standard) to draw the truth table as follows:

$$\begin{array}{c|c|c} P & Q & P\implies Q \\ \hline \text{T} & \text{T} & \text{T} \\ \hline \text{T} & \text{F} & \text{F} \\ \hline \text{F} & \text{T} & \text{T} \\ \hline \text{F} & \text{F} & \text{T} \end{array}$$

This is just a definition, but let's see what the motivation behind it is. We can interpret $P\implies Q$ as "if $P$ is true, then $Q$ must also be true". If you think a little, you will realize that "if $P$ is true, then $Q$ must also be true" is logically equivalent to "There is no case where $P$ is true and $Q$ is false". This is the only assertion of the statement and the statement makes no claim about what should happen when $P$ is false. So if there is a case where $P$ is true and $Q$ is false, then the statement becomes false, and if there is no case where $P$ is true and $Q$ is false, then the statement becomes true; Therefore, the only case that $P\implies Q$ is false, is when $P$ is true and $Q$ is false and this is exactly the motivation behind the above truth table.