One way to approach $P\to Q$ is to ask ourselves what we would expect to be the case if someone asserted, If it gets cloudy then it will rain.
On the side, we may let $P$ be "it is cloudy" and $Q$ be "it rains", but first consider what we expect when we hear that statement. There are four possibilities. We only care about the first two of them:
- It is cloudy and it rains.
- It is cloudy and it does not rain.
- It is not cloudy and it rains.
- It is not cloudy and it does not rain.
If we accept what the person said as true, then we expect the first possibility to happen. However, if the second happens, then we tell the person he was wrong. But if the last two happen, that is, if it does not get cloudy at all, we neither praise nor blame the person for good or bad information.
Now replace the sentences with the symbols using an "and" connective ($\land$):
- $P \land Q$: If this happens then the person spoke the truth.
- $P \land \neg Q$: If this happens then the person spoke a falsehood.
- $\neg P \land Q$: We don't care about this case since it did not get cloudy.
- $\neg P \land \neg Q$: We don't care about this case either since it did not get cloudy.
If we want to build a bivalent truth-functional logic we will need to do two things.
First, we have to assign a truth value to any well-formed proposition. Since this is a bivalent system we can only assign true or false values. There is no third option and any well-formed proposition has to be assigned one or the other value.
Second, any connective such as "and", "or", "not" and "implies" has to be assigned a truth value also for all possible combinations of these well-formed propositions. That is where the truth tables come in. They show all these assigned values of true or false.
This second condition raises a problem. We really don't care what truth-value we assign to the 3rd and 4th possibilities above, but we have to assign both of them some truth value. Since we don't care, it is convenient to assign them the value true. Although that might appear to be a reasonable default under the circumstances of bivalence, that's what makes this appear non-intuitive in other contexts.
Now let's go to the questions:
- How can we make intuitive sense of $\neg P \lor Q$ representing $P \to Q$?
The only time when the conditional is false is when it is cloudy and it does not rain, or $P\land \neg Q$. Suppose it is not cloudy. Then it is one of the two situations where we don't care and have assigned that true. Suppose it is cloudy. We do care about these situations. If it is cloudy then it better rain.
So, $\neg P \lor Q$, it is not cloudy or it rains, represents what we expect (with the don't-care situations taken as true) for $P\to Q$, if it is cloudy then it rains.
- Why does $P \lor \neg Q$ not represent the conditional $P\to Q$?
Remember, the only time the conditional is false is if it is cloudy and it does not rain, that is, if $P \land \neg Q$. However, if we have $P$ or $\neg Q$ we could have that situation if both of these are true. Then the conditional would be false. In that case $P \lor \neg Q$ cannot represent the conditional $P\to Q$.
If it's raining, there's a cloud in the sky. This is the same as saying that "either it isn't raining, or there is a cloud in the sky".
? – Nov 13 '16 at 13:17