(for the short attention span, it may be worth skipping the main content and just looking at the bottom to see the projective numbers)
It may be interesting to see one of the first fully rigorous accounts of the geometric sense of infinity.
In Euclidean geometry, it was realized that there was a duality between points and lines — it was realized that many theorems in the field of projective geometry were duals of one another: you could take one theorem, swap the notion of "point" and "line", fix up some details, and the result would be the other theorem.
As a simple example of this idea, "through every two distinct points there is exactly one line" becomes "on every two distinct lines there is exactly one point", which fixes up to "every pair of distinct lines is either parallel or has exactly one point of intersection".
The breakthrough came up algebraically. Recall that you can define points in the plane as a pair $(x,y)$ of coordinates, and you can define lines as triples $(a:b:c)$ of coefficients (where at least one of $a$ or $b$ is nonzero), and a point lies on a line if:
$$ ax + by + c = 0 $$
(I use colons (:) instead of commans (,) to denote that multiplying through by a nonzero constant gives the same line)
It was realized that you could improve the symmetry between points and lines by representing a point as three coordinates $(x:y:z)$ with $z \neq 0$ (corresponding to the two-coordinate form $(\frac{x}{z}, \frac{y}{z})$), and then a point lies on a line if
$$ ax + by + cz = 0$$
At this point, it is an easy step to relax the restriction on nonzero coordinates: the projective plane consists of points with coordinates $(x:y:z)$ with at least one nonzero coordinate, and lines with coefficients $(a:b:c)$ with at least one nonzero coefficient.
From the Euclidean perspective of the $(x,y)$ plane, all of those points with $z=0$ are said to be "at infinity". Now, every pair of Euclidean parallel lines does meet at a unique point at infinity. There is one additional line, the "line at infinity", which passes through all of the points at infinity.
But algebraically, it's clear that infinity is not special; it behaves just like any other place on the projective plane. In fact, if we decide to fix $y \neq 0$ and work with the $(x/y,z/y)$ coordinates, we get another Euclidean plane and most of those points that were at infinity are now ordinary Euclidean points.
And this isn't just an esoteric thing; projective coordinates are very important for doing geometry, particularly when working with perspective (e.g. computer graphics) or when doing geometry algebraically. Also when doing algebra geometrically!
If you repeat this construction with the line rather than the plane, you get the projective line. You can naturally extend arithmetic; i.e.
- $(a:b) + (c:d) = (ad+bc : bd)$
- $(a:b) - (c:d) = (ad-bc : bd)$
- $(a:b) \cdot (c:d) = (ac : bd)$
- $(a:b) / (c:d) = (ad:bc)$
where the operations are only defined if the right hand side is not $(0:0)$. As before, the colon means that $(a:b)$ and $(ac:bc)$ mean the same thing if $c \neq 0$.
Each ordinary number $x$ corresponds to the point $(x:1)$. Of particular note is that $1/0$ exists, and is $(1:0)$. It is convenient to name $\infty = (1:0)$, and so we have $1/0 = \infty$. And then we have other things like $\infty + 1 = \infty$, $1/\infty = 0$, and $\infty + \infty$ is undefined.
(in calculus, we tend to do things differently, so that we get two points at infinity, rather than just the one)