We know that any positive real number $x$ can be represented as a simple continued fraction $$x = a_{0} + \dfrac{1}{a_{1} + \dfrac{1}{a_{2} + \dfrac{1}{a_{3} + \cdots}}} = [a_{0}, a_{1}, a_{2}, a_{3}, \ldots]$$ where $a_{0}$ is a non-negative integer and $a_{1}, a_{2}, a_{3}, \ldots$ are positive integers. Moreover this representation is unique when $x$ is an irrational number. The integers $a_{i}$ will be called terms of the simple continued fraction.
Of special interest are the numbers whose simple continued fraction consists of terms in arithmetic progression (after a certain point). Two examples are $$\frac{e - 1}{2} = [0, 1, 6, 10, 14, \dots]$$ and $$\frac{e^{2} - 1}{2} = [3, 5, 7, 9, \dots]$$
Hurwitz proved in 1891 that:
If $x, y$ are two positive numbers whose simple continued fractions have terms in arithmetic progression (after a certain point) then there is no non-trivial bi-linear relation of the form $$y = \frac{Ax + B}{Cx + D}$$ with integer coefficients $A, B, C, D$ unless the terms of both the continued fractions belong to the same arithmetic progression (i.e. after a certain point the terms in the continued fraction are equal).
I need a proof of the above result. Full context of this problem is in this answer.
Update: It is easy to observe that if $x = [a_{0}, a_{1}, a_{2}, \dots], y = [b_{0}, b_{1}, b_{2}, \dots]$ and $a_{n + i} = b_{n + j}$ for all $n$ and some fixed values of $i, j$ then we do have a simple bi-linear relation between $x, y$. I believe the theorem says that only in such case (i.e. when the terms in their continued fraction are ultimately same) there can be a bi-linear relation between $x, y$. I also believe that the theorem holds in general and it is not necessary for the terms in the continued fraction to be in arithmetic progression, but I am not sure.