I would like to ask about properties that are preserved under equivalence of categories. To be more specific, is it true that equivalences preserve limits? Why?
2 Answers
Basically any property that can be considered categorical in nature. Any textbook would list a warning if a property isn't preserved. Wikipedia lists some simple examples.
Here are some things that aren't necessarily preserved:
- Number of objects
- Number of morphisms (total)
- Underlying graph
- Other evil properties
Tip for Proofs:
Equivalences preserve hom-sets. This helps, for example, if you are trying to proof that a morphism is unique.

- 10,365
-
Thanks..the problem is that I can not prove them. I have read the article on Wikipedia before but have trouble with proofs. For isomorphism of categories it is usually easy but for equivalences I need help. Would you please give me some hints on how to prove them? Thank you very much! – Ying Zhou Jul 02 '15 at 21:30
-
In Categories, Allegories, Freyd and Scedrov describe a diagrammatic form of logic. The simplest kind of proposition consists of a finite sequence of categories
$$ J_0 \xrightarrow{i_0} J_1 \xrightarrow{i_1} \ldots \xrightarrow{i_{n-1}} J_n $$
A functor $F_0 : J_0 \to C$ satisfies this statement if and only if:
- there exists a functor $F_1 : J_1 \to C$ such that $F_1 i_0 = F_0$ such that
- for every functor $F_2 : J_2 \to C$ such that $F_2 i_1 = F_1$ such that
- there exists a functor $F_3 : J_3 \to C$ such that $F_3 i_2 = F_2$ such that
- ...
For example, the proposition that a $J$-shaped diagram has a limit is given by the sequence (all of the $i$ maps are inclusions)
- $J_0 = J$
- $J_1$ is the diagram that includes the object, arrows, and equations describing a cone
- $J_2$ is the diagram that includes the object, arrows, and equations describing another cone
- $J_3$ is the diagram that includes the arrow and equations describing a morphism between the cones
- $J_4$ is the diagram that includes the arrow and equations describing another morphism between the cones
- $J_5$ includes the relations asserting both of those arrows are equal
The theorem they prove is
A proposition respects equivalence of categories if and only if it can be described on a blackboard
which is an amusing description whose actual content is
A proposition respects equivalence of categories if and only if every $i_n$ is injective on objects
The meat of the theorem is part of the canonical model structure:
A diagram of categories and functors $$ \require{AMScd} \begin{CD} A @>F>> B \\ @VGVV @VHVV \\ C @>K>> D \end{CD} $$ has the lifting property iff there exists a functor $L:C \to B$ that makes the diagram commute: that is, $F = LC$ and $K = HL$.
Theorem: If there is a specific functor $G$ such that every square where $H$ is a surjective equivalence has the lifting property, then $G$ is injective on objects
To see why this is relevant, suppose we have $$ \require{AMScd} \begin{CD} J_n @>F_n>> C \\ @Vi_nVV @VVUV \\ J_{n+1} & & D \end{CD} $$
where $U$ is a surjective equivalence. Define $G_n = U F_n$ and suppose $i_n$ is injective on objects.
Regarding satisfying propositions, we ask about the possible existence of functors $F_{n+1} : J_{n+1} \to C$ and $G_{n+1} : J_{n+1} \to D$ that satisfy $F_{n} = F_{n+1} i_n$ and $G_n = G_{n+1} i_n$, and are still related by $G_{n+1} = U F_{n+1}$.
- If we're given an $F_{n+1}$, then it's clear that we can also construct $G_{n+1}$ simply by setting $G_{n+1} = U F_{n+1}$.
- If we're given a $G_{n+1}$, then it completes the square above, and the lifting property gives us an $F_{n+1}$.
This can be used to show that $F_0 : J_0 \to C$ satisfies a sentence if and only if $U F_0 : J_0 \to D$ satisfies the sentence.
In fact, as a special kind of (co)reflection, every equivalence is (co)monadic. This can either be shown directly, or (if you are feeling trigger happy) by Beck's theorem.
– user54748 Jul 03 '15 at 01:43