Let $R$ be a commutative ring, and $n$ be a nonnegative integer. Let $f\in R\left[t,t^{-1}\right]$ be a Laurent polynomial in one variable $t$ over $R$ (this means a formal $R$-linear combination of terms of the form $f^m$ with $m\in\mathbb Z$ such that only finitely many of these terms have nonzero coefficients).
We let $f^{\prime}$ denote the derivative of $f$ with respect to $t$, defined in the formal way: $f^{\prime} = \sum\limits_{m\in \mathbb Z} mf_m t^{m-1}$, where $f_m$ is the coefficient of $f$ before $t^m$.
Theorem: The coefficient of the Laurent polynomial $f^n f^{\prime}$ before $t^{-1}$ is zero.
Let me sketch the standard proof of this theorem, to show what I want to avoid:
First of all, it is very easy to verify the Theorem in the case $n=0$. Hence, we can apply the Theorem to $f^{n+1}$ and $0$ instead of $f$ and $n$, and conclude that the coefficient of the Laurent polynomial $\left(f^{n+1}\right)^0 \left(f^{n+1}\right)^{\prime}$ before $t^{-1}$ is zero. Since
$\left(f^{n+1}\right)^0 \left(f^{n+1}\right)^{\prime} = \left(f^{n+1}\right)^{\prime} = \left(n+1\right)f^n f^{\prime}$ (by the Leibniz identity or the chain rule, as you wish),
this yields that the coefficient of the Laurent polynomial $ \left(n+1\right)f^n f^{\prime}$ before $t^{-1}$ is zero.
Now, if $n+1$ is not a zero-divisor in $R$, then this immediately yields that the coefficient of the Laurent polynomial $f^n f^{\prime}$ before $t^{-1}$ is zero. Thus, the Theorem is proven in the case when $n+1$ is not a zero-divisor in $R$. In particular, the Theorem is proven in the case when $R$ is a polynomial ring over $\mathbb Z$. But since the statement of the Theorem (for a given value of $n$ and for a given up-degree and low-degree of the Laurent polynomial $f$) is a polynomial identity in the coefficients of $f$, proving it when $R$ is a polynomial ring over $\mathbb Z$ automatically entails that it holds for any commutative ring $R$ (by an elementary fact which has many names, among them "principle of permanence of identities"). Thus, the Theorem is proven.
Question: Is there a (not too long or ugly) proof of the Theorem which avoids the use of the principle of permanence of identities? For $n=0$ and $n=1$, the Theorem can be shown by "expanding" the polynomial, but this seems to become messy for higher $n$'s. I believe there should be some smart induction-over-$n$ argument (maybe through generalization of the Theorem).