As I mentioned in the comments section of Arturo's post, $\mathbb{Q}$ is as large as possible among countable linearly ordered sets.
Said another way, if $X$ is countable an linearly ordered, then there is an order preserving injection $X\rightarrow\mathbb{Q}$. So, if one (partially) orders the set of all countable linearly ordered sets by $X\leq Y$ iff there is a 1-1 order preserving map from $X$ to $Y$, then $\mathbb{Q}$ is the largest element of this set. (To be frank, I'm not positive this satisfies the antisymmetry condition of being a partial order, but whatever).
The proof is quite constructive. The key properties of $\mathbb{Q}$ are that it has no first or last element, and inbetween any two elements of $\mathbb{Q}$ there is another one.
Using these properties, the proof goes as follows:
X is countable so list the elements $X=\{x_1,x_2,...\}$. We will inductively define a function $f:X\rightarrow \mathbb{Q}$.
To start the induction, let $f(x_1)$ be any element of $\mathbb{Q}$. Next, assume $f$ has been defined on $\{x_1,...,x_n\}$ with $f$ injective and order preserving. We now define $f(x_{n+1})$. If $x_{n+1}$ is smaller than all of the previous $x_i$, define $f(x_{n+1}) = q$ where $q$ is any rational number smaller than all of $f(x_1),...,f(x_n)$. Such a $q$ certainly exists since the set $\{f(x_1),...,f(x_n)\}$ is finite. Likewise, if $x_{n+1}$ is bigger than all the previous $x_i$, choose $f(x_{n+1})$ bigger than all of the $f(x_i)$.
Finally, we assume $x_i < x_{n+1} < x_j$ for some previously some $x_i$ and $x_j$ in $\{x_1,...,x_n\}$. Further, we choose $x_i$ from $\{x_1,...,x_n\}$ as large as possible but still less than that $x_{n+1}$, and likewise, choose $x_j$ as small as possible. Then we define $f(x_{n+1})$ to be any rational number in between $f(x_i)$ and $f(x_j)$.
By induction, $f$ is defined for all $x_i$, and this $f$ is the desired injection.
With more care, one can show that if $X$ is dense in itself with no first or last element, then we can arrange for $f$ to be surjective, showing that these properties uniquely characterize $\mathbb{Q}$ up to isomorphism! (The "more care" is to well order $\mathbb{Q}$ and at any stage where a choice is made, to choose the minimal rational number satisfies whatever it has to).