The equivalence is just equivalence in the equational $\lambda$-theory under discussion. In this case, it's the theory outlined in Table 1. Note that this theory does not include $\eta$: doing so would make the theory extensional, and the point is eventually that $\xi$ respects $\lambda$'s intensionality, while it would make CL partially extensional. I am not sure why the other answer mentions $\eta$.
Note that in $\lambda$:
$$(M =_\beta N) \Longrightarrow (\lambda x.M =_\beta \lambda x.N) \tag{1}$$
This should be intuitively obvious: if $M$ is $\beta$-convertible to $N$ when it stands by itself, then it is also $\beta$-convertible to $N$ when it is a subterm of $\lambda x.M$.
The $\xi$-rule, defined as
\begin{align}
M &\;= N \\
\hline
(\lambda x.M) &\;= (\lambda x.N)
\tag{$\xi_\lambda$}
\end{align}
makes this inference directly possible when it is part of a $\lambda$-theory. Its CL analogue would be:
\begin{align}
M &\;= N \\
\hline
(\lambda^* x.M) &\;= (\lambda^* x.N)
\tag{$\xi_{CL}$}
\end{align}
Now, the point is that in CL, the following does not hold:
$$(M =_w N) \Longrightarrow (\lambda^* x.M =_w \lambda^*x.N) \tag{2}$$
In other words, if two terms are weakly equal, then this is not necessarily true for their pseudo-abstracted versions.
Consequently, if we add $\xi_{CL}$ to a CL theory, then we start equating terms which have different normal forms.
Note. Here, $M =_w N$ denotes weak equality. It means that $M$ can be converted into $N$ (and vice versa) by a series of $\mathsf{S}$ and $\mathsf{K}$ contractions (possibly also $\mathsf{I}$, if it is part of the theory). As you probably know, $=_w$ is the CL analogue of $=_\beta$.
$\lambda^*$ is the pseudo-abstractor as defined on page 5 of your document. It has the following property:
$$(\lambda^*x.M)N \rhd_w [N/x]M \tag{3}$$
This property makes it easy to find a CL analogue for any $\lambda$-term: just change $\lambda$ to $\lambda^*$ and apply the translations according to the definition of $\lambda^*$.
To be clear, the 'counter-example' in this answer is not a counter-example to (2). Because if we have:
$$M = x \tag{4}$$
$$N = (\lambda^*z.z)x \tag{5}$$
Then $N$ really denotes (applying the translations of page 5, and the fact that $\mathsf{I}$ is defined as $\mathsf{SKK}$ at the end of page 4):
$$N = (\lambda^*z.z)x = \mathsf{I}x = \mathsf{SKK}x \tag{6}$$
Since $\mathsf{SKK}x \rhd_w \mathsf{K}x(\mathsf{K}x) \rhd_w x$, we indeed have that $M =_w N$. However, if it is a counter-example, we should then have that $(\lambda^* y. M) \not=_w (\lambda^* y. N)$. But if we translate, we actually get:
$$(\lambda^* y. M) = (\lambda^* y. x) = \mathsf{K}x \tag{7}$$
$$(\lambda^* y. N) = (\lambda^* y. \mathsf{SKK}x) = \mathsf{K}(\mathsf{SKK}x)\tag{8}$$
And is easy to verify that (7) and (8) are still weakly equal, for:
$$\mathsf{K}(\mathsf{SKK}x) \rhd_w \mathsf{K}(\mathsf{K}x(\mathsf{K}x)) \rhd_w \mathsf{K}x \tag{9}$$
Now, a proper counter-example to (2) would be:
$$M = \mathsf{K}xy$$
$$N = x$$
Since $\mathsf{K}xy \rhd_w x$, we definitely have that $M =_w N$. However, if you translate carefully for the abstracted versions, then you will see that both are distinct normal forms - and these cannot be convertible according to the Church-Rosser theorem.
First we check $M'$:
\begin{align}
M' &= \lambda^* x.\mathsf{K}xy \\
&= \mathsf{S}(\lambda^* x.\mathsf{K}x)(\lambda^* x.y)\\
&= \mathsf{S}(\lambda^* x.\mathsf{K}x)(\mathsf{K}y) \\
&= \mathsf{S}(\mathsf{S}(\lambda^* x.\mathsf{K})(\lambda^* x.x))(\mathsf{K}y) \\
&= \mathsf{S}(\mathsf{S}(\lambda^* x.\mathsf{K})(\mathsf{I}))(\mathsf{K}y) \\
&= \mathsf{S}(\mathsf{S}(\lambda^* x.\mathsf{K})(\mathsf{SKK}))(\mathsf{K}y) \\
&= \mathsf{S}(\mathsf{S}(\mathsf{KK})(\mathsf{SKK}))(\mathsf{K}y)
\end{align}
Here you can verify that $M'$ is a normal form. Here you can check that $(\lambda^* x.Kxy)P \rhd_w P$, as you should expect if $\lambda^*$ is supposed to behave like an abstractor for CL. (Click the blue links to perform weak contractions.)
Now we check $N'$:
\begin{align}
N' &= \lambda^*x.x \\
&= \mathsf{I} \\
&= \mathsf{SKK}
\end{align}
Which is obviously a normal form different from $M'$, so $M' \not=_w N'$ by the Church-Rosser theorem. Note also that $N'P \rhd_w P$, i.e. $M'$ and $N'$ 'produce the same output' for arbitrary inputs $P$.
We have now proven that (2) does not hold in CL, and that a CL theory incorporating $\xi$ would therefore equate terms that are not weakly equal. But why do we care?
Well, first of all, it makes the combinatory interpretation of $\lambda$ imperfect: apparently not all metatheoretic properties carry over.
In addition, and perhaps more importantly, while there exist extensional theories of $\lambda$ and CL, they are originally and commonly kept intensional. Intensionality is a nice property because $\lambda$ and CL model computation as process, and from this perspective two different programs (specifically, terms that have a different normal form) that always produce the same results (given equal inputs) are not to be equated. $\xi$ respects this principle in $\lambda$, and if we want to make $\lambda$ extensional, we could just add e.g. $\eta$. But the introduction of $\xi$ in CL would no longer make it completely intensional (in fact, only partially so). And this is the reason for $\xi$'s 'notoriety', as the article puts it.