About intuition.
Aristotle introduced a notion of consequence along the following lines. Suppose $A$ and $B$ are sentences, each of them either true or false. We study the relation :
(1) 'If A is true, then B has to be true too'.
Many logicians reckoned that the main use of logic is derive conclusions from premises, with the obvious goal that if we start from true premises, and we use “logical rules”, we will derive true conclusions. This idea of logic gives rise to the relation :
(2) 'From A, we can prove B'.
Now we try to translate all this into modern terms.
(1) translates into the relation of logical consequence $A \vDash B$ :
'For every interpretation $\mathcal I$, if A is true under $\mathcal I$, then B is true under $\mathcal I$.'
We “generalize” it putting in place of the sentence A a set $\Gamma$ of sentences :
$\Gamma \vDash \varphi$
which means that :
'For every interpretation $\mathcal I$, if all of $\Gamma$ are true under $\mathcal I$, then $\varphi$ is true under $\mathcal I$.'
Lastly, we have the “special acse” when $\Gamma = \emptyset$ : $\vDash \varphi$ means that the sentence $\varphi$ is valid (in propositional logic it is a tautology) when it is true under every interpretation.
In this case, we call it also logical (or universally) valid sentence, meaning that it is true “under all possible circumstances”.
For (2) [see Neil Tennant, Natural logic (1978), page 5], we have that, in order to demonstrate the validity of an argument one needs a proof.
A proof of an argument is a sequence of steps starting from its premisses, taken as starting points, to its conclusion as end. Within a proof each step, or 'inferences', must be obviously valid.
A system of proof is a codification of these obviously valid kinds of inference, which we call rules of inference. A proof in accordance with these rules must, in order to meet the demands of certainty, satisfy the following conditions :
(i) It must be of finite size.
(ii) Every one of its steps must be effectively checkable.
A system of this type is a logical calculus (i.e.proof systems) formalizing the relation of derivability :
$A \vdash B$
which is :
'B is derivable using only the logical rules of the calculus, starting from A as premise’.
We “generalize” it putting in place of the sentence A a set $\Gamma$ of sentences :
$\Gamma \vdash \varphi$.
Lastly, we have the “special case” when $\Gamma = \emptyset$ : $\vdash \varphi$ means that the sentence $\varphi$ is theorem of the calculus (it is provable) when it is derivable from no premises.
Obviously there must be no invalid proofs in our system : the system must be sound.
Moreover we wish to be able to prove any valid argument expressible in the language. The system, that is, must be complete (or adequate).
Soundness : if $\Gamma \vdash \varphi$, then $\Gamma \vDash \varphi$ (with the particular case : if $\vdash \varphi$, then $\vDash \varphi$)
<p><em>Completeness</em> : if $\Gamma \vDash \varphi$, then $\Gamma \vdash \varphi$ (with the particular case : if $\vDash \varphi$, then $\vdash \varphi$).</p>
$\models$
$\vdash$$\vdash$
and $\Rightarrow$$\Rightarrow$
. For some basic information about writing math at this site see e.g. here, here, here and here. – Martin Sleziak Apr 19 '14 at 05:10