7

Write $\mathrm{ICF}$ for the "injective continuum function hypothesis" i.e. the sentence of ZFC expressing that

$$2^X \cong 2^Y \rightarrow X \cong Y$$

for all sets $X$ and $Y$, where $\cong$ denotes equipotency.

If I understand correctly:

  1. $\mathrm{ICF}$ is independent of $\mathrm{ZFC}$.
  2. $\mathrm{GCH}$ implies $\mathrm{ICF}.$ (In the presence of the $\mathrm{ZFC}$ axioms.)
  3. The converse of 2 is false.

Question. Are there situations outside set theory (e.g. group theory, measure theory, etc.) where it would be useful if $\mathrm{ICF}$ were true, irrespective of whether or not $\mathrm{GCH}$ is true?

goblin GONE
  • 67,744

2 Answers2

10

In the theory of infinite matroids one can talk about a basis of a matroid. Higgs proved that $\sf GCH$ implies that if $\cal M$ is a matroid on a set $E$, then every two bases of $\cal M$ have the same cardinality.

However a close inspection of the proof shows that in fact we need two facts which follow from $\sf GCH$ (but do not imply it, even in conjunction):

  1. $\sf ICF$, and
  2. For every infinite set $X$ there exists a chain of subsets of size $2^{|X|}$ in $\mathcal P(X)$.

I'm not 100% sure whether or not the second is implied by the first, and I am inclined to believe that the answer to that is negative. But this is an example of somewhere that $\sf ICF$ explicitly shows up in the proof.

For some more information: Stefan Geschke - An invitation to infinite matroids (slides)

Asaf Karagila
  • 393,674
8

This is addressing two questions of user18921 asked in the comments to Asaf's answer.

a) The reason why GCH gives long chains in $\mathcal P(X)$ is the following: For an infinite cardinal $\kappa$ let $L=\{0,1\}^\kappa$ and let $B$ be the set of all sequences in $\{0,1\}^\kappa$ that are eventually 0 (or constant, it doesn't matter). The size of $B$ is $\sup\{2^\lambda:\lambda<\kappa\}$.
$L$ is linearly ordered by the lexicographic ordering and $B$ is dense in $L$. Assuming GCH we have $2^\lambda\leq\kappa$ for all $\lambda<\kappa$ (this is all of GCH that we need). Hence $|B|=\kappa$. Let $X=B$. Now the family of sets $\{x\in B:x<y\}$, $y\in L$, is a chain in $\mathcal P(X)$ of size $2^{|X|}$.

b) (2) is equivalent to (2'). One half of this is already hidden in my answer a): If there is an infinite linear order of size $|X|$ whose completion is of size $2^{|X|}$, then $\mathcal P(X)$ has a chain of length $2^{|X|}$.

On the other hand, assume $\mathcal P(X)$ has a chain $\mathcal C$ of length $2^{|X|}$. We may assume that $\mathcal C$ is closed under infinite intersections and that it contains $X$. Now for each $x\in X$ consider the first $A\in\mathcal C$ with $x\in A$ and call it $A_x$. By our assumptions on $\mathcal C$, $A_x$ exists for all $x\in X$. It is just the intersection of all $A\in\mathcal C$ with $x\in A$.

Now $\mathcal A=\{A_x:x\in X\}$ is a dense subset of the linearly ordered set $\mathcal C$ ($\mathcal C$ is ordered by $\subseteq$, of course). $\mathcal A$ is a linear order of size $|X|$ with a completion of size $2^{|X|}$.

The equivalence of (2) and (2') was observed independently by Baumgartner and Mitchell, if I remember correctly.