Nope. Unfortunately, what you have written is not rigorous enough. Here is an argument. (In general, whenever you want to prove that some set is infinite, assume it is finite and using the elements construct another element which is not in the set. This is in the spirit of Euclid's argument for infinitude of primes.)
Let $S_{\Omega} = \{f: \Omega \rightarrow \Omega | f \text{ is bijective}\}$. We shall first prove that $S_{\Omega}$ is an infinite set. Assume that $S_{\Omega}$ has only finitely many elements, say $N$ of them. Let them be $f_1,f_2,\ldots,f_N$. We shall denote each $f_k$ as follows. $$f_k = \{a_{k1},a_{k2},\ldots,a_{kn},\ldots \}$$ where $a_{kl} = f_k(l)$. We then have the following.
$\begin{array}{ccc}
f_1 & = & \{a_{11},a_{12},a_{13},\ldots,a_{1N},\ldots\}\\
f_2 & = & \{a_{21},a_{22},a_{23},\ldots,a_{2N},\ldots\}\\
f_3 & = & \{a_{31},a_{32},a_{33},\ldots,a_{3N},\ldots\}\\
\vdots & \vdots & \vdots \\
f_N & = & \{a_{N1},a_{N2},a_{N3},\ldots,a_{NN},\ldots\}\\
\end{array}$
Let $M = \max \{a_{11},a_{22},a_{33},\ldots,a_{NN}\}$. We shall now construct a $f$ which is a bijection from $\Omega$ to $\Omega$ but doesn't match with any of the $f_k$'s above.
$$f(m) = \left \{ \begin{array}{lr} M+m & m \in \{1,2,\ldots,M\}\\ m-M & m \in \{M+1,M+2,\ldots,2M\}\\ m & m \geq 2M+1 \end{array} \right.$$
Clearly, $f$ is a bijection from $\Omega$ to $\Omega$. In-fact, the inverse of $f$ is itself. It is also easy to check that $f$ doesn't match with any of the $f_k$'s. If $f$ were to match with $f_k$ for some $k$, then we must have $f_k(k) = f(k)$. However, we have that $f_k(k) = a_{kk} \leq M < M+k = f(k)$. Hence, $f$ doesn't match with any of the listed $f_k$'s. This is true for any $N \in \mathbb{N}$. Hence, the set $S_{\Omega}$ is an infinite set.
Now we need to prove that $S_{\Omega}$ is a group.
Consider $f_1,f_2 \in S_{\Omega}$. Let $f = f_1 \circ f_2$. If we have $f_1( f_2 (a_1)) = f_1( f_2 (a_2))$, then since $f_1$ is a injective, we have $f_2(a_1) = f_2(a_2)$ and since $f_2$ is a injective, we get $a_1 = a_2$. Hence, $f_1 \circ f_2$ is injective. Given any $c \in \{1,2,3,\ldots\}$, since $f_1$ is surjective, $\exists b \in \{1,2,3,\ldots\}$ such that $f_1(b) = c$. Since $f_2$ is surjective, $\exists a \in \{1,2,3,\ldots\}$ such that $f_2(a) = b$. Hence, $\exists a \in \{1,2,3,\ldots\}$ such that $f_1(f_2(a)) = c$. Hence, $S_{\Omega}$ is closed under function compositions.
The associativity follows from the fact that composition of functions is associative.
The map $f(n) = n$, $\forall n \in \Omega$ acts as the identity map since for any $g \in S_{\Omega}$, we have $g(f(n)) = g(n)$ and $f(g(n)) = g(n)$.
For any $f \in S_{\Omega}$, since $f$ is a bijection, there exists an inverse map, $g$, which is also a bijection and hence $g \in S_{\Omega}$. Hence, any element in $S_{\Omega}$ has an inverse.
Hence, $S_{\Omega}$ is a group under function compositions.