Consider a typical proof in an introductory analysis course:
Claim: Let $(x_n)_\mathbb{N}$ and $(y_n)_\mathbb{N}$ be convergent sequences in $\mathbb{R}$ (or $\mathbb{C}$) and let $x,y$ be their respective limits. Then $(x_n+y_n)_\mathbb{N}$ is convergent and its limit is $x+y$.
Proof: Let $\varepsilon >0$. There exists $n_1$ resp. $n_2$ such that $$\forall n \geq n_1, |x_n-x| < \varepsilon/2$$ resp. $$\forall n \geq n_2, |y_n - y| < \varepsilon/2.$$ Let $n_0 = \max(n_1,n_2).$ The triangle inequality implies that $$\forall n \geq n_0, |(x_n + y_n) - (x+y)| \leq |x_n - x| + |y_n - y| < \varepsilon/2 + \varepsilon/2 = \varepsilon.$$ This proves the claim.
As a first-year student, this is a proof structure that comes up a lot. And yet, a significant portion of it seems redundant. Namely, the actual value of $n_0$ that I chose is of almost no significance. I could just as well have chosen $n_1 + n_2$ or $\max(n_1,n_2)+52.$
The only thing that's important is that $n_0$ be greater than both $n_1$ and $n_2$, which is necessarily possible due to the fact that $\mathbb{N}$ is totally-ordered and not bounded above.
This remark has led me to come up with a notation which I use extensively in my notes and saves me vast amounts of ink. This notation is the following:
I define the notation $\mathbb{N}^\infty$ to mean “any set of the form $\mathbb{N}\setminus \left\{0,\ldots,n_0\right\}$ where $n_0 \in \mathbb{N}$. (The $\infty$-symbol is supposed to symbolise “sufficiently close to infinity”.) Like little-oh and big-oh notation, $\mathbb{N}^\infty$ does not refer to a specific object but rather a generic object with a certain property. However, $\mathbb{N}^\infty$ sets have the following useful property: any finite intersection of $\mathbb{N}^\infty$ sets is $\mathbb{N}^\infty$. (This is kind of like how any finite sum of $o(f)$ functions is $o(f).$)
The last property has the following consequence:
Let $P_1,\ldots,P_k$ be predicates on $\mathbb{N}.$ Suppose that for all $i=1,\ldots,k$ we have $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty,P_i(n) \textrm{ is true}.$$ Then $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty, (P_1(n)\wedge\ldots\wedge \ P_k(n)) \textrm{ is true}$$
This is just a fancy way of saying “If, in a finite set of predicates, each predicate is true for sufficiently large $n$, then for sufficiently large $n$, each predicate is simultaneously true.” Note that this fails if the number of predicates is infinite.
Using this notation, the definition of the limit can be written as follows:
We say that $(x_n)_\mathbb{N}$ tends to some number $x$ iff for all $\varepsilon >0,$ $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty, |x_n - x| < \varepsilon.$$
Using the property that I just stated, proof I gave above can also be rewritten:
Proof: Let $\varepsilon >0$. Then $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty,|x_n - x| < \varepsilon/2$$ and $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty,|y_n - y| < \varepsilon/2$$ hence by the triangle inequality, $$\forall n \in \mathbb{N}^\infty,|(x_n+y_n) - (x+y)| < \varepsilon.$$
Not only is this version more concise, but in my opinion it is better from a pedagogical point of view. When a student unfamiliar with analysis reads the first version (see above), there is some chance that we will be side-winded by the construction of $n_0$ (which as I said bears little to no importance), and he will be detracted from the actual crux of the proof which is the use of the triangle inequality. On the other, if the same student reads the second version, assuming that he understands the notation, he won't be side-winded by information that is not strictly necessary to his conceptual understanding of the proof. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, there is no loss in rigour in using the $\mathbb{N}^\infty$ notation provided that the “rules of the game” are well-understood.
In a similar vein, for functional limits I use the notation $I^a$ (where $I$ is an interval and $a$ is in the closure of $I$) to signify “the intersection of $I$ with some open interval centred around $a$”. Here, the $a$ in the exponent is intended to symbolise “sufficiently close to $a$”. We again have the property that any finite intersection of $I^a$ sets is $I^a$.
In a way that is similar to the above, this notation allows us to simplify definitions and proofs in a way that is in my opinion non-negligeable and pedagogically fruitful.
Finally, I would like to ask:
Since the notions of “sufficiently large” and “sufficiently close to” are so ubiquitous in analysis, why haven't mathematicians come up with a way to convey them efficiently?