24

We know that if $f\in L^1(\mathbb{R})$, then $\|f(\cdot+1/n)-f(\cdot)\|_{L^1}\to 0$ as $n\to \infty$, which implies that there exists a subsequence $f_{n_k}=f(x+\frac{1}{n_k})$ such that $f_{n_k}\to f$ a.e.

My problem is that Is there any $f\in L^1(\mathbb{R})$ function such that the almost convergence result $$ f(x)=\lim_{n\to\infty}f(x+1/n)\quad \text{a.e.} $$ is NOT valid? I intend to believe that there exits such function. Otherwise, there would be a beautiful statement such that $f(x)=\lim_{n\to\infty}f(x+1/n)$ a.e. for any $f\in L^1(\mathbb{R})$.

Thank you for the long commenting below @David C. Ullrich. This question has been reduce to find a compact set $K$ such that for any $x\in K$, there are infinite $n$ such that $x+\frac{1}{n}\not\in K$.

Yuhang
  • 1,575

7 Answers7

8

I submit that we can show that the a.e. convergence property $$\tag{FALSE} f(x+\tfrac1n)\to f(x)\qquad x\text{-a.e.}\quad \forall\, f\in L^1(\mathbb T). $$ does NOT hold by using Stein's maximal principle (thank you David C.Ullrich for pointing this out). This has the advantage of a simpler proof at the expense that we won't produce an explicit counterexample. (EDIT. See David C.Ullrich's answer for such counterexample).

Definitions. For $f\in L^1(\mathbb T)$ we define the maximal function $$ f^\star(x)=\sup_{n\in \mathbb N} |f(x+\tfrac1n)|.$$ To show that Stein's maximal principle does not hold we need to construct a sequence $(f_k)_{k\in \mathbb N}$ in $L^1(\mathbb T)$ such that $$ \frac{\|f_k^\star\|_{1,\infty}}{\|f_k\|_1}\to +\infty, $$ where the weak $L^1$ norm is defined as $$ \|g\|_{1,\infty} =\sup_{t>0} t|\{x\in\mathbb T\ :\ |g(x)|>t\}|,$$ and $|A|$ for a set $A\subset \mathbb T$ denotes Lebesgue measure.

Proof. The sequence $f_k$ is defined as $$ f_k(x)=k^2\mathbf 1_{\{|x|\le \frac1{k^2}\}}.$$ We have $$f_k^\star(x)\ge \sup_{1\le n \le k} |f_k(x+\tfrac1n)|=\sum_{n=1}^k k^2\mathbf1_{\{|x+\tfrac1n|\le\frac1{k^2}\}}=:k^2\mathbf1_{A_k}.$$ Notice that $A_k$ is the union of $k$ disjoint intervals of length $1/k^2$. Using this observation we can bound from below the weak $L^1$ norm as $$ \|f_k^\star\|_{1,\infty}\ge \|k^2\mathbf1_{A_k}\|_{1,\infty}=k. $$ Since $\|f_k\|_1=1$ for all $k$, the proof is complete. $\square$

Remark. Here we considered functions on the torus $\mathbb T=\mathbb R/\mathbb Z$, because the Stein maximal principle needs a compact group structure. This is not a real limitation, because the statement (FALSE) is local in nature. If such a statement were true for $f\in L^1(\mathbb R)$ it would also be true for functions supported on bounded intervals, and this we disproved.

  • 1
    Fabulous - I can't believe I missed this. Btw getting from here to an explicit counterexample is easier than the proof of Stein's theorem, because we can arrange things so that $\sum m(supp(f_k))<1$. See newest answer... – David C. Ullrich Jan 23 '18 at 15:36
  • 2
    For anyone interested, this argument extends easily to arbitrary sequences of (distinct) offsets $a_n$ instead of $1/n.$ Just replace the $1/k^2$ by $\min_{1\leq n,m\leq k} |a_n-a_m|.$ – Dap Jan 23 '18 at 17:27
  • Although it does not construct any counterexample, I have to say this is the most beautiful answer. That is why I have to give you bounty. Thx. – Yuhang Jan 24 '18 at 01:30
  • @Yuhang: I am so glad you liked it. Thank you for reading and for your kind words. – Giuseppe Negro Jan 24 '18 at 06:43
  • @GiuseppeNegro: It seems that I keep stumbling upon solutions you wrote a couple of years later. There is a couple of recent (as of 2021) problems and there that are in a sense the same as the one you worked on here. In my solution to the former I also used switched to $\mathbb{T}$ and used Stein-Sawyer's maximal principle; but later on I found a pure real line theorem (Stein) that I used in the other problem. – Mittens May 01 '21 at 23:35
  • @GiuseppeNegro: my point being is that Stein's maximal principle for convolutions with measures with common support allows to keep the problem within $\mathbb{R}$. In any case, I do like the construction of your function $f_k$. I used a slightly different argument and showed only existence. – Mittens May 01 '21 at 23:37
  • @oliverdiaz: I have noticed your comment, I am just struggling to find the time to read your answer carefully. That is very interesting. The question is roughly the same as this one. I liked your observation linking pointwise convergence to convolution with deltas. – Giuseppe Negro May 06 '21 at 12:02
  • @GiuseppeNegro: thanks for your message. It is always a pleasure to discuss mathematics with you (if only through MSE). I was looking at the example of David C. Ulrich. I have not digested it yet, but I can see that it is a probabilistic argument of your construction. The interesting thing, is that in his use of "random translations" to apply a Borel-Cantelli type of argument, is exactly what Stein (in terms of beautiful analysis) does in his proof of the theorem of convolutions. I tried to explain that it my posting. – Mittens May 06 '21 at 14:38
  • @GiuseppeNegro:The source I used is Stein's Harmonic Analysis, p.p. 440-444. – Mittens May 06 '21 at 14:40
7

Not an answer - two long comments for the benefit of anyone who's looking for that counterexample that "must" exist:

First, I realized the other day that the sort of construction I'd been trying cannot possibly work. To save others from attempting the impossible:

Say $f$ is a counterexample. Say $(n_j)$ is a bad sequence for $x$ if $$|f(x)-f(x+1/n_j)|>\epsilon$$for all $j$. The sorts of constructions I'd been thinking about, fat Cantor sets, etc., would have had this property if successful:

There exists a single sequence $S=(n_j)$ such that $S$ is a bad sequence for $x$, for all $x$ in some set of positive measure.

That's impossible. Given $S$, the set of $x$ such that $S$ is bad for $x$ must have measure zero. Because there does exist a subsequence of $S$ giving convergence almost everywhere.

(To be specific: I noticed that if $C$ is the standard Cantor set then for all but countably many $x\in C$ we have $x+1/3^n\notin C$. So $\chi_C$ would be a counterexample, except $m(C)=0$. This got me thinking about fat Cantor sets. The above shows that if a fact Cantor set does give a counterexample the explanation cannot be that simple; it cannot be that "uniform".)

In the other direction:

If there is a counterexample then there is a counterexample of the form $\chi_K$ for some compact $K$.

This follows from Lusin's theorem. Say $f$ is a counterexample. There exists $[a,b]$ such that if $E$ is the set of bad points in $[a,b]$ then $m(E)>0$. Suppose that $K\subset[a,b]$ is compact, $m(K)+m(E)>b-a$, $g$ is continuous, and $g=f$ on $K$. If $x\in K\cap E$ then we must have $x+1/n\notin K$ for infinitely many $n$. Since $m(K\cap E)>0$ this shows that $\chi_K$ is a counterexample.

6

This question has been reduce to find a compact set $K$ such that for any $x\in K$, there are infinite $n$ such that $x+\frac{1}{n}\not\in K$".

As I have understood David C. Ullrich's answer, it is also required that $m(K)>0$.

I just received a letter from Taras Banakh with the following

Corollary. For any decreasing sequence $(a_n)_{n=1}^\infty$ of positive real numbers with $\lim_{n\to\infty}a_n=0$ and $\lim_{n\to\infty}\frac{a_{n+1}}{a_n}=1$, there exists a compact subset $K\subset\mathbb R$ of positive Lebesgue measure such that $\bigcap_{n=m}^\infty(K-a_n)=\emptyset$.

Corollary follows from Theorem, see below.

Let $\mathcal K(\mathbb R)$ be the space of non-empty compact subsets of the real line, endowed with the Vietoris topology (which is generated by Hausdorff metric). It is well-known that the space $\mathcal K(\mathbb R)$ is locally compact (more precisely, each closed bounded subset of $\mathcal K(\mathbb R)$ is compact.

For every $c>0$ let $\mathcal K_c(\mathbb R)=\{K\in\mathcal K(\mathbb R):\lambda(K)\ge c\}$ be the subspace of consisting of compact sets $K$ of Lebesgue measure $\lambda(K)\ge c$. The regularity (or countable additivity) of the Lebesgue measure $\lambda$ implies that $\mathcal K_c(\mathbb R)$ is a closed subspace in $\mathcal K(\mathbb R)$. Consequently the space $\mathcal K_c(X)$ is locally compact and Polish.

Theorem. Let $(a_n)_{n=1}^\infty$ be a decreasing sequence of positive real numbers such that $\lim_{n\to\infty}a_n=0$ and $\lim_{n\to\infty}\frac{a_{n+1}}{a_n}=1$. Then for every $c>0$ the set $$\{K\in\mathcal K_c(X):\forall m\in\mathbb N\;\bigcap_{n=m}^\infty(K-a_n)=\emptyset\}$$ is dense $G_\delta$ in $\mathcal K_c(X)$.

Proof. It suffices to prove that for every $m\in\mathbb N$ the set $$\mathcal K_m=\{K\in\mathcal K_c(X):\bigcap_{n=m}^\infty(K-a_n)=\emptyset\}$$ is open and dense in $\mathcal K_c(X)$.

To see that $\mathcal K_n$ is open, take any compact set $K\in\mathcal K_m$. By the compactness of $K$, there exists $l>m$ such that $\bigcap_{n=m}^l(K-a_n)=\emptyset$. Then for every $x\in \mathbb R$ there exists $n_x\in[m,l]$ such that $x\notin K-a_{n_x}$. So, we can find a symmetric neighborhood $U_x\subset[-1,1]$ of zero such that $x+U_x$ is disjoint with $U_x+K-a_{n_x}$. By the compactness of the set $L=[-1,1]+(K-a_m)$, there exists a finite subset $F\subset L$ such that $L\subset\bigcup_{x\in F}(x+U_x)$. We claim that the open neighborhood $\mathcal U=\{K'\in\mathcal K_c(X):K'\subset\bigcap_{x\in F}(K+U_x)\}$ of $K$ in $\mathcal K_c(X)$ is contained in the set $\mathcal K_m$. Assuming that $\mathcal U\not\subset\mathcal K_m$, we can find a compact set $K'\in\mathcal U\setminus \mathcal K_m$. Since $K'\notin\mathcal K_m$, there exists a point $z\in \bigcap_{n=m}^\infty (K'-a_n)$. It follows that $z\in K'-a_m\subset [-1,1]+K-a_m=L$ and hence $z\in x+U_x$ for some $x\in F$. Then $$z\in (x+U_x)\cap\bigcap_{n=m}^\infty K'-a_n\subset (x+U_x)\cap (K'-a_{n_x})\subset (x+U_x)\cap (U_x+K-a_{n_x})=\emptyset,$$ which is a desired contradiction, showing that $\mathcal U\subset\mathcal K_m$ and the set $\mathcal K_m$ is open in $\mathcal K_m$.

Next, we show that $\mathcal K_m$ is dense in $\mathcal K_c(\mathbb R)$. Given any $K\in\mathcal K_c(\mathbb R)$ and $\varepsilon>0$ we need to find a set $K'\in\mathcal K_m$ on the Hausdorff distance $d_H(K',K)<\varepsilon$ for $K$.

Choose $k\ge m$ so large that $\frac1k<\frac12\varepsilon$. Consider the cover $\mathcal I_k=\big\{\big[\frac{n}k,\frac{n+1}k\big]:n\in\mathbb N\big\}$ of $\mathbb R$ by closed intervals of length $\frac1n$. The choice of $k$ ensures that the compact set $\tilde K=\bigcup\{I\in\mathcal I_n:I\cap K\ne\emptyset\}$ has $d_H(\tilde K,K)\le \frac1k<\frac12\varepsilon$. Also it is clear that $\tilde K$ has Lebesgue measure $\lambda(\tilde K)>\lambda(K)\ge c$. Choose $p\ge k$ so large that $(1-\frac1p)\cdot\lambda(\tilde K)\ge c$.

Since $\lim_{n\to\infty}\frac{a_{n+1}}{a_n}=1$, there exists $q>p$ such that $\frac{a_{n+1}}{a_{n}}>1-\frac1{4p}$ for all $n\ge q$. Finally, take $l>q$ such that $\frac2{lk}<a_q$. Consider the open set $$Z:=\bigcup_{z\in\mathbb Z}{\big]}\tfrac{z}{kl},\tfrac{z}{kl}+\tfrac1{pkl}{\big[}$$ and observe that for every interval $I\in\mathcal I_k$ the set $I\setminus Z$ has Lebesgue measure $\lambda(I\setminus Z)=(1-\frac1p)\lambda(I)$ and Hausdorff distance $d_H(I,I\setminus Z)<\frac12\varepsilon$. Consequently, the compact set $K'=\tilde K\setminus Z$ has Lebesgue measure $\lambda(K')=(1-\frac1p)\cdot\lambda(\tilde K)\ge c$ and $d_H(K',\tilde K)=\frac1{2pkl}<\frac12\varepsilon$. Then $d_H(K',K)\le d_H(K,\tilde K)+d_H(\tilde K,K)<\varepsilon$. It remains to prove that $K'\in\mathcal K_m$. Assuming that $K'\notin\mathcal K_m$, we could find a point $x\in\bigcap_{n=m}^\infty (K'-a_n)$. Then $x+a_n\in K'\subset\mathbb R\setminus Z$ for all $n\ge m$. Let $z\in Z$ be the unique integer number such that $\frac{z-1}{lk}<x\le \frac{z}{lk}$. The choice of $l$ guarantees that $\frac2{lk}<a_q$. Then $\frac{z+1}{lk}=\frac{z-1}{lk}+\frac2{lk}<x+a_q$. Let $i\ge q$ be the smallest number such that $x+a_i\ge \frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{plk}$. Then $x+a_{i+1}<\frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{plk}$ and hence $a_{i+1}<\frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{plk}-x<\frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{plk}-\frac{z-1}{lk}= \frac1{lk}+\frac1{plk}<\frac2{lk}$.

On the other hand, $$a_i-a_{i+1}=a_{i+1}\tfrac{a_i}{a_{i+1}} (1-\tfrac{a_{i+1}}{a_i})<\tfrac2{lk}(1-\tfrac1{4p})^{-1}\tfrac1{4p}<\tfrac1{lkp}$$ and hence $x+a_{i+1}>x+a_i-\frac1{lkp}\ge\frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{plk}-\frac1{plk}=\frac{z}{kl}$. Then $\frac{z}{kl}<x+a_{i+1}<\frac{z}{lk}+\frac1{lkp}$ implies that $x+a_{i+1}\in Z$, which is a desired contradiction, completing the proof of $K'\in\mathcal K_m$.$\square$

PS. Also Taras Banakh sent to me the reference to the talk “Theorems of H. Steinhaus, S. Picard and J. Smital” by W. Wilczyński from Ger-Kominek Workshop in Mathematical Analysis and Real Functions 20-21.11.2015.

At the last page are stated the following results.

Theorem. If $A\subset\Bbb R$ is a measurable set, then for each sequence $\{x_n\}_{n\in\Bbb N}$ convergent to $0$ the sequence of characteristic functions $\{\chi_{A+x_n}\}_{n\in\Bbb N}$ converges in measure to $\chi_A$.

Remark. There exists a measurable set $A\subset\Bbb R$ and a sequence $\{x_n\}_{n\in\Bbb n}$ convergent to $0$ such that $\{\chi_{A+x_n}\}_{n\in\Bbb N}$ does nor converge almost everywhere to $\chi_A$.

Theorem. If $A$ has the Baire property, then $\{\chi_{A+x_n}\}_{n\in\Bbb N}$ converges to $\chi_A$ except on a set of the first category.

Alex Ravsky
  • 90,434
  • Three years later but it does not matter. There is a recent posting to which there result you presented seems to fit right in. What is puzzling, is that the OP on the link I mentioned, is from a textbook and gives a seemingly simple hint of a fat Cantor set. Looking at this now, I believe the problem is much harder than the simple hint seems to indicate. – Mittens May 01 '21 at 23:58
5

This is similar to Alex Ravsky's answer, but just answering exactly the question and nothing more. Define

$$K_d=\bigcup_{k=0}^{2^d-1} (k2^{-d}+2^{2-2d},(k+1)2^{-d})\subset [0,1]\qquad\text{for }d\geq 10$$ $$K=\bigcap_{d\geq 10}K_d.$$

It is easy to compute $\mu([0,1]\setminus K_d)=2^{2-d}$ which gives $\mu(K)\geq 1/2.$ I claim that for all $x\in[0,1]$ and for all $d\geq 10$ there is some $n$ with $2^{d-1}\leq n\leq 2^d$ such that $x+1/n\notin K_d$ - this would imply that $x+1/n\notin K$ for infinitely many $n,$ which suffices to answer the question.

Geometrically/intuitively: There is a distance of less than $2^{2-2d}$ between consecutive elements in the list $x+1/2^d, x+1/(2^d-1), \dots, x+1/2^{d-1}.$ This means that as we go along the list we cannot jump over a gap of length $2^{2-2d}.$ And the difference between the first and last elements of the list is $2^{-d}.$ Since $K_d$ has gaps of size $2^{2-2d}$ at every multiple of $2^{-d},$ not every element in the list can be in $K_d.$

Algebraically: set $n=\lfloor 1/(k2^{-d}-x)\rfloor$ where $k=\lceil x2^d\rceil+1.$ Note that $2^{d-1}\leq n\leq 2^d,$ because $1\leq k-x2^d\leq 2.$ Since $1/(n+1)\leq k2^{-d}-x\leq 1/n$ and $1/n-1/(n+1)=1/n(n+1)<1/n^2\leq 2^{2-2d},$ we have $k2^{-d}-x\leq 1/n\leq k2^{-d}+2^{2-2d}-x.$ So $x+1/n\notin K_d$ as required.

Dap
  • 25,286
  • I found this proof easier – ibnAbu Jan 23 '18 at 10:34
  • Your proof also works if you replace {$n$} with another countable set {$E_n$} for which $E_n \to \infty$ as $n \to \infty$ – ibnAbu Jan 23 '18 at 13:09
  • @Abdullahi_A_Ibrahim: I don't think it does. We need that the set $E={E_n}$ can be split into sets $D_d$ such that the sumset $D_d+C_d$ contains $[0,1],$ for some sets $C_d$ of measure tending to zero as $d\to\infty.$ For $E_n=1/n$ the sets $D_d={1/2^d,1/(2^d-1),\dots,1/2^{d-1}}$ have the property of having similar-sized gaps between consecutive elements, which allows a particularly simple $C_d$ - just a union of evenly-spaced intervals. For $E={2^{-n}}$ for example, it's not so obvious what to use as $D_d$ and $C_d.$ – Dap Jan 23 '18 at 16:45
  • The pairs $C_d,D_d$ are essentially the "complementary sets" described in the abstract of https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s006050300001, so I think they do exist, but it takes more work. I can't access that article, but discrete analogues are proved in https://arxiv.org/abs/0910.3815 using a greedy algorithm. – Dap Jan 23 '18 at 16:48
  • If you are interested in arbitrary offsets, Giuseppe Negro's proof is likely the easiest way to go. You might need the full Stein theorem rather than the cheap version in David C. Ullrich's answer. – Dap Jan 23 '18 at 17:46
  • i noticed for all $ x \in K_d $ there some $ p $ , $ 2^{2-2d} \le p < 2^{-d} $ such that $ x+p \notin K_d $ , $ p $ not need to be $\in N $ – ibnAbu Jan 23 '18 at 20:57
  • $ p $ not need to be $ p=\frac {1}{m} $ where $ m \in N $
  • – ibnAbu Jan 24 '18 at 05:23
  • And $$ \bigcup_{d \ge 10}[2^{2-2d} , 2^{-d})=[0, 2^{-10}) $$ – ibnAbu Jan 24 '18 at 09:23
  • @Dap It seems clear to me that the cheap arguument suffices in the more general case, Say $I_k$ and $A_k$ are the sets analogous to $I_k$ and $A_k$ in his and my constructions. We need to have $m(I_k)/m(A_k)\to0$ or the argument showing the maximal function does not satisfy the appropriate bound doesn't work.Now if $m(I_k)/m(A_k)\to0$ then passing to a subsequence we have $\sum m(I_k)<\infty$, $\sum m(A_k)=\infty$, and the randomization argument I gave works with no change. – David C. Ullrich Jan 24 '18 at 13:25
  • @DavidC.Ullrich: it's not clear to me why $\sum m(A_k)=\infty.$ I can see why we could assume $m(A_k)\geq \tfrac12 k \cdot m(I_k).$ But what about $m(I_k)=2^{-k}$ for example? – Dap Jan 24 '18 at 14:46
  • @Dap Fair point. It appears that I lied; $m(I_k)/m(A_k)\to0$ does not imply what I said about those sums. Now we have a new problem to think about... – David C. Ullrich Jan 24 '18 at 15:04
  • @DavidC.Ullrich: I think your argument can be generalized by replacing $I_k$ by the union of $\lceil (k^2c_k)^{-1}\rceil$ independent copies, where $c_k$ is the replacement for "$1/k^2$" – Dap Jan 24 '18 at 16:43