I'm reading Paolo Aluffi's ALGEBRA, Chapter 0.
Here he proposes that there's a thorny issue:
What is this thorny issue?
I'm reading Paolo Aluffi's ALGEBRA, Chapter 0.
Here he proposes that there's a thorny issue:
What is this thorny issue?
The non-emptyness of this set cannot be deduced from the usual nine axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Instead, it needs to be postulated as a separate axiom, the axiom of choice. Some (but these days only very few) people do not like to assume the axiom of choice in their mathematics, because it has some counter-intuitive consequences (but omitting it does, too!).
As Aluffi hints at, the thorny issue is that the nonemptiness of the Cartesian product of an arbitrary family of nonempty sets is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. There are situations where the Axiom of Choice is not required to show that the Cartesian product is nonempty:
However, it can happen (if Choice fails) that $S_n$ is nonempty and finite (even of cardinality $2$) for each $n \in \mathbb{N}$, yet $\prod_{n} S_n$ is empty.
I don't think I say too much by declaring that the vast majority of mathematicians today fully accept the Axiom of Choice, as it has many helpful consequences/equivalents (e.g., every vector space has a basis, cardinalities of sets are always comparable, the product of compact spaces is compact) and by itself it cannot add contradictions to set theory (if ZFC is inconsistent, then so is ZF).
For more information, consider looking at any number of answers by Asaf from this list of questions.
The assumption that the product of non-empty sets is non-empty is known as the axiom of choice (note that every function in the product is a choice function, so the assertion that the product is non-empty is exactly the assertion that there is a choice function).
The axiom of choice has a myriad of counterintuitive consequences, like the Banach-Tarski paradox for example. There has been quite some troubles with the axiom of choice when it was first proposed, but with time it was shown that new no contradictions are added if we assume it, or if we assume that it fails. Since then a lot of mathematicians rather just assume it in order to tame the way infinite objects behave.
If the collection $\ell$ is finite, then we can prove that the product is non-empty without the axiom of choice. However if the collection itself is infinite, then we need the axiom of choice for the proof. Of course there are some collections which we can prove to have non-empty products without the axiom of choice, for example a collection of singletons, or finite sets of real numbers, but generally speaking one needs the axiom of choice.
Also related: